Acessibilidade / Reportar erro

Therapeutic limitation for children with severe brain malformations

Abstract

Brain malformations may present themselves in different forms, from mild to severe, which can be lethal within a few hours after birth. Based on a systematic review of literature, it was verified that, although theoretically suspending or withholding treatment are ethically similar, in practice, such equivalence is not perceived either by doctors and nursing assistants or by the general population, who tend to more comfortably accept the withholding rather than the withdrawal of treatments. The dialogue with parents is the procedure that legitimizes medical initiatives when proposing therapeutic limitation. In conclusion, severe brain malformations result in an end of life context, in which bioethical principles of palliative care apply and in which the limitation of respiratory support is the main dilemma to be faced in the final moments of patients’ lives.

Keywords:
Hydrocephalus; Microcephaly; Medical futility; Corpus callosum; Chromosomes-Pathology

Resumo

As malformações cerebrais congênitas podem se apresentar de forma leve ou grave, podendo ser letais mesmo poucas horas após o nascimento. A partir de levantamento bibliográfico sistemático, verificou-se que, embora em tese sejam eticamente semelhantes suspender e renunciar a tratamento, tal equivalência não é percebida na prática por médicos e enfermeiros assistentes, nem pela população em geral, que tende a aceitar mais confortavelmente a renúncia que a suspensão de tratamentos. O diálogo com os pais é o procedimento que legitima a iniciativa médica de propor limitação terapêutica. Em conclusão, as malformações cerebrais graves resultam em contexto de terminalidade de vida, em que limitação ao suporte respiratório é o principal conflito enfrentado e ao qual se aplicam princípios bioéticos dos cuidados paliativos.

Palavras-chave:
Hidrocefalia; Microcefalia; Futilidade médica; Corpo caloso; Cromossomos-Patologia

Resumen

Las malformaciones cerebrales congénitas pueden presentarse desde formas leves hasta formas graves, pueden ser letales pocas horas después del nacimiento. A partir de una revisión bibliográfica sistemática se verificó que, aunque teóricamente suspender o reiniciar un tratamiento es éticamente semejante, esta equivalencia no es percibida en la práctica ni por los médicos y enfermeros asistentes, ni por la población en general, que tiende a aceptar más cómodamente la renuncia que la suspensión de los tratamientos. El diálogo con los padres constituye el procedimiento que legitima la iniciativa médica de proponer la limitación terapéutica. En conclusión, las malformaciones cerebrales graves dan lugar a un contexto de terminalidad de la vida, en el cual se aplican los principios bioéticos de los cuidados paliativos, y en el que la limitación del soporte respiratorio es el principal conflicto que se enfrenta en los momentos finales de la vida del paciente.

Palabras clave:
Hidrocefalia; Microcefalia; Inutilidad médica; Cuerpo calloso; Cromosomas-Patología

The history of what may be called a good, or “happy”, death probably began in Suetonius's work “The Lives of the Twelve Caesars”, dating from the second century AD, which contains a description of the tranquil, swift death of Emperor Augustus 11. Junges JR. Bioética: hermenêutica e casuística. São Paulo: Loyola; 2006.. This is a term that has been adopted by the medical community, which aims to minimize the suffering within the context of the end of a person's life. The right to life is guaranteed by human dignity; however, in a situation involving terminal illness, the tension that is inherent to the topic itself is evident and is indicative of the need to continually improve the technical and ethical aspects of such situations in order to better manage death in medical terms22. Rodrigues CFA. Alteridade da morte de Emmanuel Levinas. Rev. bioét. (Impr.). 2012;20(3):442-50.,33. Taboada P. El derecho a morir con dignidad. Acta Bioeth. 2000;6(1):89-101..

Medical responsibility is a principle of the utmost importance not only in terms of bioethical analysis, but also in taking the decision to bring forth elements that highlight the asymmetry between doctor and patient and the protection of this relationship under law. Unforeseeable accidents and uncontrollable maladies exist, which arise from situations that involve an inexorable progression, independent of the efforts of the medical professionals and staff, and which are related to the intrinsic mortality of every living being44. Marreiro CL. Responsabilidade civil do médico na prática da distanásia. Rev. bioét. (Impr.). 2013;21(2):308-17.. Caring for terminally ill patients increases the responsibility of the health care professional, who finds himself weakened when he administers such care to patients due to the inevitable association between responsibility, risk and guilt, especially regarding the possible non-compliance of the professional with ethical and legal obligations55. Junges JR, Cremonese C, Oliveira EA, Souza LL, Backes V. Reflexões legais e éticas sobre o final da vida: uma discussão sobre a ortotanásia. Rev. bioét. (Impr.). 2010;18(2):275-88..

The complexity of events that are involved with terminal illness represents a challenge for professionals in this field66. Kipper DJ. O problema das decisões médicas envolvendo o fim da vida e propostas para nossa realidade. Bioética. 1999;7(1):59-70.. This is a paradox, which, in every sense of the word, fragments the understanding of the bioethical principles in a frontier realm, providing a stage for different ethical and moral, bioethical and deontological, regulatory, legal and administrative discourses.

The terminal nature of life is an even greater encumbrance when it involves children that have incurable chronic diseases that will not allow them to live for very long. In other words, when, during the life cycle of an individual, birth and death become temporally proximate. Congenital malformations are examples of these clinical conditions, and, in general, such deformities can be expressed in various degrees of severity, from relatively mild, which will not significantly reduce the individual's life expectancy, to more severe forms, which will become lethal only a few hours after birth.

Children that have cerebral malformations that evolve into a terminal clinical condition evoke moral and, therefore, bioethical dilemmas that can be classified at the crossroads between fundamental concepts found among neuroethics, the ethics involved in palliative care and the ethics of pediatric care. These children are, generally, submitted to treatments that are clearly intensive and obstinate, but there are also situations in which the obstinacy is not so obvious.

In the vast majority of countries, pediatric care is not characterized by the heteronomy of the child, that is, its legal incapacity to decide for him or herself; the child must be represented by a responsible adult, which is generally the parents or some other representative that has been legally appointed. However, there are bioethical issues regarding the limits of this protection and the margin of parental decision-making in light of potentially lethal clinical conditions, especially when differences arise between the desires of the parents and the duties of the medical staff.

The treatment of terminal patients requires the application of health care practices that are based on there not being a chance of curing the patient 77. Academia Nacional de Cuidados Paliativos. Manual de cuidados paliativos. Rio de Janeiro: Diagraphic; 2009.. The dignity of human life which has passed on must be respected, and, because of this, the decision to perform adequate treatment to maintain the life of a patient and mitigate suffering in a manner that does not increase the individual's pain and discomfort are ethical issues that are relevant when one is treating children with severe brain malformations. In each situation, for each patient, circumstances may arise in which it becomes clear that therapeutic obstinacy is being undertaken, but there will also always be situations where the limits are imprecise, where the best path to take is not clearly visible88. Villas-Bôas ME. Da eutanásia ao prolongamento artificial. Rio de Janeiro: Forense; 2005.,99. Souza PVS. O médico e o dever legal de cuidar: algumas considerações jurídico-penais. Bioética. 2006;14(2):229-38..

Deep geopolitical differences exist between countries where palliative care and therapeutic restrictions have been legally implemented and have become both routine and ethically recognized in medical practice, and those countries where terminal care tend to be more obstinate, which make constant use of intensive technologies1010. Lien Foundation. The 2015 quality of death index: Ranking palliative care across the world. London: The Economist Intelligence Unit; 2015.. Brazil is considered to be at an intermediate stage because, despite the fact that therapeutic obstinacy has not been set forth in the country's legal code, ethical standards have already been developed and submitted by the Conselho Federal de Medicina (CFM) (Federal Council of Medicine) with respect to the limitation of therapy when dealing with patients that are terminally ill.

Considering the above, and based on a review of the literature, the present article has the following objectives. 1) to analyze the peculiarities that exist in addressing palliative care and therapeutic restrictions in caring for the health of children that possess brain malformations; 2) to identify the principal invasive therapeutic procedures in caring for the health of these children; 3) to delimit the ethical and conceptual difference between “obligatory care” and “therapeutic obstinacy” when caring for the health of children that have brain malformations; and 4) to analyze the bioethical boundaries of the decisions of those that are responsible when faced with the heteronomy of these children.

Methodology

A systematic revision of relevant journal articles was conducted, during which these articles, in accordance with Marconi and Lakatos 1111. Marconi MA, Lakatos EM. Técnicas de pesquisa. 7ª ed. São Paulo: Atlas; 2012., had their sources identified. The articles themselves were then located, compiled and cataloged. To identify the sources, indexation catalogs were used from the ISI Web of Science, the Biblioteca do Centro Latino-Americano e do Caribe de Informação em Ciências da Saúde (BIREME) (Latin American and Caribbean Center on Health Services Information), the Scientific Electronic Library Online (SciELO) and Google Scholar. Initially, a search was conducted by cross-referencing the keywords “ethics”, “palliative care” and “child”. The system returned more than 20 thousand possible bibliographic references. In order to narrow down the total number of articles, researchers opted to select articles that were published up to 2015.

In light of this result, researchers attempted to refine the search by adding “and not cancer”, since the cases that are the focus of this paper are not related to oncology. As such, the search attained the objective of focusing on the issue of cerebral malformation/lesions. The sources that were taken from each indexation catalog were then cross-referenced. The sources were listed and searched for within the open access portals known as Periódicos Capes and Research Gate, in addition to a direct search that was conducted using the Google search tool. Through the cataloging of each source, data was extracted regarding the illness that gave rise to the child receiving palliative care; treatments and procedures that are characteristic of therapeutic obstinacy; bioethical limits of the exercise of heteronomy by the responsible adult; and ethical and legal consequences and restrictions that arise when recommending the use of palliative care techniques. The data was compared in order to reveal which thoughts, fundamental aspects, concepts and paradigms the authors agreed and disagreed upon. This process of analyzing the data was conducted in accordance with the feedforward model, i.e., the analyzes that had already been completed provided guidance for the following analyzes, and, as a result, some papers that addressed pathologies that did not involve the brain were maintained in the sample because they discussed bioethical issues that were relevant to the subject matter.

Results and discussion

Bibliometrics

The systematic review of literature found 119 papers, of which 67 were obtained in their entirety1212. Ambler J. When is the right time? Complex issues around withdrawing life-sustaining treatment in children. S Afr Med J. 2014;104(7):507-9.7878. Zinner SE. The use of pediatric advance directives: a tool for palliative care physicians. Am J Hosp Palliat Care. 2008;25(6):427-30.. The clinical cases that were studied were related to a variety of disorders; however, a preponderance of neurological disorders was encountered, which elucidates how neuroethical issues stand out within the field of pediatric palliative care. The disorders that were identified included: severe cerebral palsy1212. Ambler J. When is the right time? Complex issues around withdrawing life-sustaining treatment in children. S Afr Med J. 2014;104(7):507-9.; severe heart failure due to inoperable cardiomyopathy 1616. Cadell S, Ho G, Jacques L, Wilson K, Davies B, Steele R. Considerations for ethics in multisite research in pediatric palliative care. Palliat Med. 2009;23(3):274-5.; spinal muscular atrophy2727. Frader J, Michelson K. Can policy spoil compassion? Pediatr Crit Care Med. 2007;8(3):293-4.,5252. Okhuysen-Cawley R, McPherson ML, Jefferson LS. Institutional policies on determination of medically inappropriate interventions: use in five pediatric patients. Pediatr Crit Care Med. 2007;8(3):225-30.; Duchenne muscular dystrophy3131. Gerhardt CA, Grollman JA, Baughcum AE, Young-Saleme T, Stefanik R, Klopfenstein KJ. Longitudinal evaluation of a pediatric palliative care educational workshop for oncology fellows. J Palliat Med. 2009;12(4):323-8.,5050. Morrison W, Berkowitz I. Do not attempt resuscitation orders in pediatrics. Pediatr Clin North Am. 2007;54(5):757-71.; persistent coma due to the accidental lesion of a patient already suffering from incurable intracranial neoplasia3232. Geller G, Harrison KL, Rushton CH. Ethical challenges in the care of children and families affected by life-limiting neuromuscular diseases. J Dev Behav Pediatr. 2012;33(7):548-61.; respiratory insufficiency due to pulmonary hemosiderosis3636. Himelstein BP, Hilden JM, Boldt AM, Weissman D. Pediatric palliative care. N Engl J Med. 2004;350(17):1752-62.; Down's Syndrome associated with degenerative encephalopathy4242. Lago P, Devictor D, Piva JP, Bergounioux J. Cuidados de final de vida em crianças: perspectivas no Brasil e no mundo. J Pediatr. 2007;83(2 Suppl):S109-15.; kidney transplant and persistent coma due to accidental trauma4444. Levetown M. Communicating with children and families: from everyday interactions to skill in conveying distressing information. Pediatrics. 2008;121(5):e1441-60.; trisomy 18 with operable heart disease4545. Levine DZ. Discontinuing immunosuppression in a child with a renal transplant: are there limits to withdrawing life support? Am J Kidney Dis. 2001;38(4):901-15.; terminal cystic fibrosis4545. Levine DZ. Discontinuing immunosuppression in a child with a renal transplant: are there limits to withdrawing life support? Am J Kidney Dis. 2001;38(4):901-15.; inborn error of metabolism with persistent coma4747. Martin C. Deception and the death of Ilyusha: truth and the best interest of a dying child in The Brothers Karamazov. Pediatrics. 2014;134(2 Suppl):s87-96.; and Proteus syndrome6969. Torres JCT, Goya JLH, Rubia NH, Jimenez PN, Munóz FG, Rodríguez JP et al. Recomendaciones sobre toma de decisiones y cuidados al final de la vida en neonatología. An Pediatr. 2013;78(1):190.e1-14..

The papers that were researched gave a well-founded day-to-day overview of the bioethical conflicts regarding palliative care techniques that become standard practice, i.e., which have become associated with therapeutic restrictions. Therapeutic restrictions therefore represent extreme cases of palliative care techniques with respect to which bioethical conflicts have become significant. In essence, the ethical-legal basis for this issue, according to Lago et al.4242. Lago P, Devictor D, Piva JP, Bergounioux J. Cuidados de final de vida em crianças: perspectivas no Brasil e no mundo. J Pediatr. 2007;83(2 Suppl):S109-15., resides in the fact that terminal medical care techniques, in the final analysis, become a public health care issue.

Overview of pediatric palliative care techniques

The papers that were selected and analyzed were in agreement that the ethical dilemma surrounding therapeutic restrictions has emerged in conjunction with the significant progress that has been made with respect to biomedical technology. A situation of inertia arises for the doctor and for the judicial framework of society when the full breadth of biomedical technology is put to use indiscriminately, despite the deleterious effects that are inherent to vital life support mechanisms, mainly those that are the most invasive. Regarding this aspect, Sayeed6464. Sayeed SA. Baby doe redux? The Department of Health and Human Services and the Born-Alive Infants Protection Act of 2002: a cautionary note on normative neonatal practice. Pediatrics. 2005;116(4):e576-85. states that poorly written laws, which are also in disagreement with the reality of clinical practices, stagnate the resolution of serious issues and worsen the possibilities of treating the group that is most at risk - namely, patients receiving terminal care.

Mercurio et al.4848. Mercurio MR, Murray PD, Gross I. Unilateral pediatric “do not attempt resuscitation” orders: the pros, the cons, and a proposed approach. Pediatrics. 2014;133(1 Suppl):S37-43. color coded a set of countries as follows: green, indicating those countries that have explicit laws that recognize the need to impose therapeutic restrictions; yellow, indicating those countries in which the situation is not defined, but tend to accept such restrictions; and red, indicating those countries where any discussion of the subject is rejected. Durall et al. 2121. Durall A, Zurakowski D, Wolfe J. Barriers to conducting advance care discussions for children with life-threatening conditions. Pediatrics. 2012;129(4):e975-82. provides examples and states that, in Russia, discussion of the issue is not allowed and the subject of therapeutic restrictions may not be publicly addressed. As a result, the majority of the bioethical debates that were encountered were submitted by authors from countries in which therapeutic restrictions have already been incorporated into the country's laws, so that conflicts are shown to contain a higher level of complexity.

In theory, according to Pelant et al.5353. Pelant D, McCaffrey T, Beckel J. Development and implementation of a pediatric palliative care program. J Pediatr Nurs. 2012;27(4):394-401., adequate palliative care services avoid the need for hospitalization, isolation and unnecessary invasive techniques with respect to terminal healthcare procedures. However, Lago et al.4242. Lago P, Devictor D, Piva JP, Bergounioux J. Cuidados de final de vida em crianças: perspectivas no Brasil e no mundo. J Pediatr. 2007;83(2 Suppl):S109-15. warned that, with respect to the pediatric age range, terminal care procedures have been undertaken more frequently in intensive care units (ICUs). Such cases generate clear ethical conflicts, since ICUs are structured to provide intensive care procedures, whereas terminally ill patients require palliative care and therapeutic restrictions.

Regarding this issue, a study by Ramnarayan et al.5959. Ramnarayan P, Craig F, Petros A, Pierce C. Characteristics of deaths occurring in hospitalized children: changing trends. J Med Ethics. 2007;33(5):255-60. showed that adults who are nearing the end of their lives prefer to die at home, whereas terminally ill children tend to pass away in a hospital environment, and, most frequently, in ICUs, in which a condition of therapeutic obstinacy is in place. Accordingly, Rezzónico6262. Rezzónico CA. Bioética y derechos de los niños. Arch Argent Pediatr. 2004;102(3):214-9. proposes that terminal care techniques should be based on the refusal of the practice of therapeutic obstinacy, i.e., in the refusal of the monolithic use of medical technology even when it is clear that the patient is going to die shortly thereafter. Generally speaking, treatment procedures that are painful and ineffective are rejected or suspended1212. Ambler J. When is the right time? Complex issues around withdrawing life-sustaining treatment in children. S Afr Med J. 2014;104(7):507-9.,7878. Zinner SE. The use of pediatric advance directives: a tool for palliative care physicians. Am J Hosp Palliat Care. 2008;25(6):427-30.; however, this is not to say that the patient is ever abandoned and does not receive care. The health care professionals simply no longer make use of advanced medical techniques and, in lieu of these procedures, administer medications that alleviate the patient's symptoms and perform basic care on the individual. In other words, a terminal patient that is receiving palliative care procedures should not be submitted to an ICU. Hospitals make other sectors available to such patients – such as the infirmary, or a room, or a day-bed – which are more appropriate for the care of terminally ill individuals.

Morgan4949. Morgan D. Caring for dying children: assessing the needs of the pediatric palliative care nurse. Pediatr Nurs. 2009;35(2):86-90. compares the recommendation for therapeutic restrictions with respect to adults - which, by convention, considers six months to be a statistically foreseeable time period for the onset of death, which is assumed to be an initial condition for the refusal or suspension of treatment – with the procedures that are adopted for the patients that are within the pediatric age range, whose statistically foreseeable time period for the onset of death has not been established by the medical community.

Leeuwenburgh-Pronk et al.4343. Leeuwenburgh-Pronk WG, Miller-Smith L, Forman V, Lantos JD, Tibboel D, Buysse C. Are we allowed to discontinue medical treatment in this child? Pediatrics. 2015;135(3):545-9. note that the heteronomy of the child exists for the purposes of his protection, due to the immaturity that is inherent to this period within an individual's life cycle. When this essential principal is set before the case of a child that suffers from a chronic disease which has severely reduced his life expectancy, the ethical and legal conflicts that arise regarding therapeutic restrictions reflect a conflict of interests between the values of the sacrosanctity of life and the maintenance of one's quality of life. Both are expressions of overall societal values which only manifest themselves in practical terms within real-world cases. Geller et al. 3232. Geller G, Harrison KL, Rushton CH. Ethical challenges in the care of children and families affected by life-limiting neuromuscular diseases. J Dev Behav Pediatr. 2012;33(7):548-61. have reaffirmed this point of view, since the conflict becomes even more powerful with respect to children.

In such cases, the conflict regarding which value should prevail is intensified. One can either take into account giving the child another day of life, which may be priceless; or, on the contrary, consider at what point the lack of quality of life should enter into the assessment. As an example, Klein4141. Klein SM. Moral distress in pediatric palliative care: a case study. J Pain Symptom Manage. 2009;38(1):157-60. mentions the case in which an infant who has holoprosencephaly with severe respiratory morbidity has undergone prolonged treatment at an ICU, and is therefore in a situation in which therapeutic restrictions would be recommended. However, in unexpected fashion, this baby recovered demonstrably well after being discharged and developed into a toddler of pre-school age without presenting any severe new health issues.

Cases such as this one raise the issue of expected time limits regarding the imposition of therapeutic restrictions; should such restrictions be proposed in situations where death is expected to occur within six months, such as is the case with adults? Or should other factors be taken into account, such as the probability of survival, and up to what age - ten years of age, adolescence or onward towards adulthood should be taken into consideration? The literature shows that the issue is still open.

To suspend versus renounce treatment

The majority of the papers that were evaluated address the ethical-legal debate regarding the difference between suspending and renouncing the use of treatment techniques. The theoretical conclusions that were reached by the authors state that the suspension or refusal of certain treatments is ethically equivalent; however, in practice, doctors, nurses and the general population believe that it is more acceptable to renounce the use of these treatments than to suspend them.

Tsai7171. Tsai E. Withholding and withdrawing artificial nutrition and hydration. Paediatr Child Health. 2011;16(4):241-2. states that the evaluation of the beneficial and deleterious effects of suspending treatment has already been made possible. As a result, the suspension of advanced life support techniques brings with it a foreseeable estimation of when death will occur, and that the perception of this expectation would be tantamount to equating the suspension of treatment with the concept of euthanasia. In this respect, legally speaking, the term “euthanasia” is applied when an explicit request has been made by the patient to allow his death to occur, whereas the suspension of inefficacious and obstinate treatment procedures in fact constitutes palliative care measures. In practice, the act of renouncing the use of advanced medical treatment implies the substitution of more invasive treatment for other procedures that, although they may be less efficacious, result in the perception that the patient's life is ending “naturally”7171. Tsai E. Withholding and withdrawing artificial nutrition and hydration. Paediatr Child Health. 2011;16(4):241-2..

An elegant resolution of this conflict of values can be found in the statistical work that was completed by Tan et al.6767. Tan GH, Totapally BR, Torbati D, Wolfsdorf J. End-of-life decisions and palliative care in a children's hospital. J Palliat Med. 2006;9(2):332-42., in which these researchers established, in mathematical terms, that both the perception of common sense and the ethical viewpoint are correct. The authors present a Kaplan-Meier survival curve for groups that consist of patients that are submitted to a “refusal” and a “suspension” of treatment. In the initial phase, both groups presented the same indices of mortality; however, once the initial phase had been surpassed, the “refusal” group surprisingly presented greater survival rates than the “suspension” group. In other words, when certain invasive treatments are suspended or are renounced altogether, the event of death will be predictably more immediate in patients whose conditions are more serious. However, a significant proportion of patients may survive longer, indefinitely - from a few days to many weeks, if, instead of intensive and invasive procedures, these patients receive adequate palliative care techniques.

In any case, Klein4141. Klein SM. Moral distress in pediatric palliative care: a case study. J Pain Symptom Manage. 2009;38(1):157-60. notes that, when treatment is suspended and death does not occur shortly thereafter, parents tend to question whether or not the diagnosis of terminal disease was truly correct. As a result, decisions involving therapeutic restriction are frequently overturned, which heighten bioethical conflicts about the breaching the doctor-patient bond of trust, which is perfectly understandable in light of the significant subjective nature of the anxiety and responsibility that befalls the parents in the face of their child's imminent death. This breach of trust highlights the deep desire of the parents in removing, or at least protecting, their child from suffering during their final moments.

Ethical procedures in deciding to restrict therapeutic procedures

Forty-six of the papers that were evaluated mentioned the issue of the decision-making process that is involved in restricting therapeutic procedures. The issue of the child's dependence and their incapacity to express their desires fully has always been presented not as a barrier to the implementation of therapeutic restrictions, but as a factor that generates special cases of ethical conflict. For purposes of comparison, Siegel et al.6666. Siegel AM, Sisti DA, Caplan AL. Pediatric euthanasia in Belgium: disturbing developments. Jama. 2014;311(19):1963-4. have stated that child euthanasia, which is legal in Holland and Belgium7979. Silva FM, Nunes R. Caso belga de eutanásia em crianças: solução ou problema? Rev. bioét. (Impr.). 2015;23(3):475-84., is a procedure that is broadly addressed within the legal codes of these countries, within which the public prosecutor evaluates the decision-making process with respect to the exercise of legal precepts. Such instances do not constitute an analysis of merit, but merely a process of establishing that each of the formal phases of the process were complied with.

In light of this fact, Morrison and Kang 5151. Morrison W, Kang T. Judging the quality of mercy: drawing a line between palliation and euthanasia. Pediatrics. 2014;133(1 Suppl):s31-6. established that the decision to restrict therapeutic procedures in an ICU, albeit a difficult one, has already become commonplace, so that the medical staff, who understand and have had extensive daily experience with the case, are responsible for the decision-making process. In other words, the authors defend that institutional ethical committees are an essential requirement, but argue that their role should be to act as a supervisory committee for resolving conflicts as they arise.

In each of the texts that were obtained, the value of maintaining communication with parents is clearly evident as a procedure that legitimizes the implementation of therapeutic restrictions. An additional consensus is that the implementation of therapeutic restrictions must be established by the medical staff; such a suggestion only arises from the parents in limited cases. In summary, the literature review shows that proper communication and decision-making procedures and conditions should be in place. Firstly, the medical treatment staff, consisting of doctors, nurses and physical therapists, should, during their daily visits, agree amongst themselves that the implementation of therapeutic restrictions is the best option for that patient. As a result, the parents of the child are invited to meetings with said hospital staff, which should occur in a room that is appropriate to this end.

During the first meeting, the subject is addressed and time is given for the parents to reflect on the issue; in a subsequent meeting, the decision to implement therapeutic restrictions is taken. In some cases, parents feel insecure, thereby making it necessary to hold more meetings. Some authors 1414. Bovens L. Child euthanasia: should we just not talk about it? J Med Ethics. 2015;41(8):630-4.,7575. Vose LA, Nelson RM. Ethical issues surrounding limitation and withdrawal of support in the pediatric intensive care unit. J Intensive Care Med. 1999;14(5):220-30. have described open and honest techniques of communication with the parents of terminally ill children. The issue of communication has been under debate since at least 1969, when Philip Evans and Cicely Saunders2222. Evans P, Saunders C. The management of fatal illness in childhood. Proc R Soc Med. 1969;62:15-7. confronted the culture of the time with respect to the death of children. Evans wrote that the doctor presented a strong, involuntary, emotional reaction to the point of weeping with the parents that lost their child, while Saunders emphasized the necessity of showing empathy, albeit with a certain emotional detachment, to make it possible for the family members to receive adequate support for their loss. Even now, not only the doctor but also nursing professionals need to know how to emotionally deal with the terminal nature of life within the field of pediatrics4949. Morgan D. Caring for dying children: assessing the needs of the pediatric palliative care nurse. Pediatr Nurs. 2009;35(2):86-90., which strengthens the argument for the need of these professionals to conduct regular clinical visits to ICUs.

The implementation of therapeutic restrictions is not an untimely measure, nor is it a matter of urgency; it is a decision that it taken in stages in light of the chronic nature of the situation. In other words, the doctor, in facing a critical situation, has the responsibility and ample freedom to prescribe and initiate treatment procedures. However, when dealing with the issue of therapeutic restrictions, the decision-making process must be shared with the parents or with those that are responsible for the child. The implementation of therapeutic restrictions is, above all, a decision that is taken within the institution by the medical treatment staff; such a decision cannot be left to the discretion of the medical chief of staff or doctor that is on-call.

The literature review revealed that two legal stances have been established that identify cases in which therapeutic restrictions may be considered legitimate. In the United States, such restrictions are legal, albeit profoundly dependent upon the agreement that is reached with the parents. The decision of not resuscitating the child, for example, must be stated in writing and signed by the responsible adults. In other countries, such as France and Japan, the paradigm of non-objection is adhered to, which is to say that the medical staff proposes the adoption of therapeutic restrictions that are implemented should the parents not object. For some scholars4242. Lago P, Devictor D, Piva JP, Bergounioux J. Cuidados de final de vida em crianças: perspectivas no Brasil e no mundo. J Pediatr. 2007;83(2 Suppl):S109-15.,1717. Clark J, Dudzinski D. The culture of dysthanasia: attempting CPR in terminally ill children. Pediatrics. 2013;131(3):572-80., in light of the emotional vulnerability that the families are subjected to, the non-objection paradigm is a form of alleviating the weight upon the parents of having to make that decision by transferring the burden to the health care staff so that the parents do not, in the future, feel guilt for having made that decision.

The more enlightened legal provisions that exist regarding the natural clinical progression of terminal illnesses and clinical indicators that can point to the onset of such disorders, the more secure and precise the medical initiatives that propose therapeutic restrictions will be1515. Brook L, Hain R. Predicting death in children. Arch Dis Child. 2008;93:1067-70.. Feudtner and Nathanson2525. Feudtner C, Nathanson PG. Pediatric palliative care and pediatric medical ethics: opportunities and challenges. Pediatrics. 2014;133(1 Suppl):s1-7. note that certain consolidated statistical data may offer guidance for the establishment of certain provisions and standard procedures; however, in practice, it is not possible to foresee the prognosis of a specific patient, i.e., such a procedure is essentially intuitive. Therefore, due to the principle of uncertainty, an open and honest discussion must be held between the medical staff and those that are responsible for the patient. Palliative care has been the subject of trailblazing studies, and Cadell et al.1616. Cadell S, Ho G, Jacques L, Wilson K, Davies B, Steele R. Considerations for ethics in multisite research in pediatric palliative care. Palliat Med. 2009;23(3):274-5. also note the importance of conducting interdisciplinary studies on the subject of palliative care techniques. In light of the sensitive nature of the issue, investigative studies of this type have revealed that even research ethics committees have professed deep disagreement regarding the established standard procedures.

For example, until recently, an ethical debate existed concerning the deep sedation of a patient during the terminal phases of cancer, under the pretense that the lifespan of the sedated patient would be reduced. However, in other studies that have examined existing literature6767. Tan GH, Totapally BR, Torbati D, Wolfsdorf J. End-of-life decisions and palliative care in a children's hospital. J Palliat Med. 2006;9(2):332-42.,5151. Morrison W, Kang T. Judging the quality of mercy: drawing a line between palliation and euthanasia. Pediatrics. 2014;133(1 Suppl):s31-6., it was noted that, although, theoretically speaking, high doses of analgesic drugs and sedatives may inhibit the patient's respiratory control centers, the group of patients that received higher doses survived longer than the group that did not receive such doses. These scholars feel that the study that was performed on palliative care techniques set the stage for the emergence of procedures for the administration of sedatives and analgesic drugs incrementally as required by the patient. By adopting such procedures of applying such treatments incrementally, high doses of analgesic and sedative medication may be used on patients that need them without any form of distrust emerging regarding the possible reduction of the lifespan of that patient.

Despite the ongoing communication between the medical staff and those that are responsible for terminally ill children, ethical conflicts of interest remain regarding the decision-making process. Ham3434. Ham C. Tragic choices in health care: lessons from the child B case. BMJ. 1999;319(7219):1258-61. mentions the case of the parents of an English child that requested further treatment for their child, even though it went against the wishes of the medical staff. The parents wanted to try a second bone marrow transplant, which the doctors were against. The English courts decided in favor of the position of the doctors, which considered such a procedure to be futile and obstinate.

Feltman et al.2323. Feltman D, Stokes T, Kett J, Lantos JD. Is treatment futile for an extremely premature infant with giant omphalocele? Pediatrics. 2014;133(1):123-8. also describe a peculiar case involving severe comorbidities - extreme prematurity and omphalocele. The parents insistently requested that the infant be subjected to a surgical procedure and, afterwards, to cardiorespiratory resuscitation techniques; however, the medical staff foresaw that such procedures would not prove effective. Such cases reveal that an ethical and legal tendency exists which favors the decision of the medical treatment staff in not implementing treatment techniques in situations where clinical conditions are unfavorable or that are contrary to medical principles. In other words, it is more acceptable to renounce certain forms of treatment than to have them suspended.

Another type of conflict arises when doctors prescribe the suspension or reduction of treatment procedures and the parents wish to have them maintained. It is understood that such a conflict of interests should not be discussed during the first meetings between the medical staff and the parents or caretakers; it should only be mentioned once this objection is voiced repeatedly. To avoid or minimize the emergence of such a situation, the proposal for restricting therapy should be introduced gradually during the mid-term planning stages as signs emerge that progressive and irreversible clinical deterioration has begun. Such a restriction should not be proposed at the last moment, in accordance with the principles of palliative care.

Notwithstanding the above, various studies1313. Basu RK. End-of-life care in pediatrics: ethics, controversies, and optimizing the quality of death. Pediatr Clin North Am. 2013;60(3):725-39.,2121. Durall A, Zurakowski D, Wolfe J. Barriers to conducting advance care discussions for children with life-threatening conditions. Pediatrics. 2012;129(4):e975-82.,2727. Frader J, Michelson K. Can policy spoil compassion? Pediatr Crit Care Med. 2007;8(3):293-4.,4949. Morgan D. Caring for dying children: assessing the needs of the pediatric palliative care nurse. Pediatr Nurs. 2009;35(2):86-90. have attempted to establish that, within such circumstances, an ethics supervisory committee (such as an institutional ethics supervisory board) may be consulted, and, in extreme cases, a request may be forwarded to the local courts. Powell5656. Powell R. Dilemmas in the medical treatment of patients facing inevitable death. Arch Dis Child. 2007;92(9):746-9. furthermore argues that, although therapeutic restrictions have not been formally accepted, the medical staff is not ethically obligated to prescribe invasive intensive care procedures, such as the constant collection of blood samples, the monitoring of the patient with electrodes (which requires a certain immobilization of the patient), the maintenance of the patient's water balance with a catheter, and so forth.

Legal opinion regarding this issue varies from country to country. Scholars5252. Okhuysen-Cawley R, McPherson ML, Jefferson LS. Institutional policies on determination of medically inappropriate interventions: use in five pediatric patients. Pediatr Crit Care Med. 2007;8(3):225-30.,6363. Ruppe MD, Feudtner C, Hexem KR, Morrison WE. Family factors affect clinician attitudes in pediatric end-of-life decision making: a randomized vignette study. J Pain Symptom Manage. 2013;45(5):832-40. have described the tendency in the US of forcing doctors to conduct routine intensive care procedures if the patient does not expressly agree with the implementation of therapeutic restrictions. Only in specific situations, which are very well supported by pre-existing standard procedures, such as terminal neoplasia or extreme prematurity6969. Torres JCT, Goya JLH, Rubia NH, Jimenez PN, Munóz FG, Rodríguez JP et al. Recomendaciones sobre toma de decisiones y cuidados al final de la vida en neonatología. An Pediatr. 2013;78(1):190.e1-14., represent an exception to this tendency. In the UK, however3434. Ham C. Tragic choices in health care: lessons from the child B case. BMJ. 1999;319(7219):1258-61.,7777. Wilfond BS. Tracheostomies and assisted ventilation in children with profound disabilities: navigating family and professional values. Pediatrics. 2014;133(1 Suppl):S44-9., the overall trend has been to uphold the decisions and standard procedures of the doctors should diverse health service staff display a consensus regarding the futility of continued therapeutic procedures.

Gunn et al.3333. Gunn S, Hashimoto S, Karakozov M, Marx T, Tan IKS, Thompson DR et al. Ethics roundtable debate: child with severe brain damage and an underlying brain tumour. Crit Care. 2004;8(4):213-8. discussed the critical situation of a patient that had a brain tumor, which would reduce his life expectancy, however, due to respiratory morbidity, the patient succumbed to a prolonged vegetative state. According to the authors, the prevailing ethical-legal stance that exists within the United States would have been more forceful than that of other countries in terms of suspending treatment even if it were against the wishes of the patient's relatives. For example, in Singapore, Japan, Germany and Russia, the moment of parental grieving and the advanced medical care procedures would be allowed to progress until the parents were comfortable with the situation. According to Schildmann et al.6565. Schildmann J, Hoetzel J, Baumann A, Mueller-Busch C, Vollmann J. Limitation of treatment at the end of life: an empirical-ethical analysis regarding the practices of physician members of the German Society for Palliative Medicine. J Med Ethics. 2011;37(6):327-32., in Germany, one can find resistance to the practices of therapeutic restriction, which were used abusively during the period of Nazism, such that it is easier to not protect someone with treatment than to suspend some type of life support.

Current treatments that will be suspended/renounced

With respect to therapeutic restrictions, the first decision to be taken involves the order not to initiate cardiopulmonary resuscitation77. Academia Nacional de Cuidados Paliativos. Manual de cuidados paliativos. Rio de Janeiro: Diagraphic; 2009., a procedure whose overall rate of efficiency is approximately 30%. In cases of terminally ill patients, such a patient may survive after resuscitation procedures have been initiated; however, the chances that they will be discharged from the hospital are still very slim. In other words, the acceptance of this therapeutic restriction is profoundly symbolic. The order to not resuscitate means that the patient and his family members recognize the medical diagnosis of the terminal nature of the clinical situation, and that a possible increase in the duration of their loved one's life will be brief and that no mechanisms exist for controlling the disease.

Although Feltman et al. 2323. Feltman D, Stokes T, Kett J, Lantos JD. Is treatment futile for an extremely premature infant with giant omphalocele? Pediatrics. 2014;133(1):123-8. argue that any treatment may be evaluated with respect to its suspension or renouncement, more drastic decisions regarding ethics fall upon the procedure of artificial breathing/mechanical ventilation support and enteral nourishment, each of them presenting peculiar ethical aspects. Advanced support for mechanical ventilation through the insertion of orotracheal intubation represents a treatment method that is too invasive and painful, and frequently requires strong sedatives and analgesic medicine in order to be introduced or maintained. Notwithstanding, the suspension of mechanical ventilation methods usually causes death in a short time span, which leads to the question of where the boundary lies between therapeutic restriction and euthanasia.

In light of the limits that have been established in this line of questioning, scholars5151. Morrison W, Kang T. Judging the quality of mercy: drawing a line between palliation and euthanasia. Pediatrics. 2014;133(1 Suppl):s31-6.,6060. Rapoport A, Shaheed J, Newman C, Rugg M, Steele R. Parental perceptions of forgoing artificial nutrition and hydration during end-of-life care. Pediatrics. 2013;131(5):861-9. warn that, since the concept of therapeutic restriction is quite new, it becomes necessary, in addition, to create a vocabulary that can abstractly describe the nuances that are involved in the clinical situations that are experienced. In other words, practical terms must be coined that make clear the proper distinction between negligence, therapeutic restriction and euthanasia.

Geller et al.3232. Geller G, Harrison KL, Rushton CH. Ethical challenges in the care of children and families affected by life-limiting neuromuscular diseases. J Dev Behav Pediatr. 2012;33(7):548-61. affirmed that respiratory care presents possibilities that are less drastic and invasive than mechanical ventilation. It is possible to apply non-invasive care or even ventilatory care via a tracheostomy instead of orotracheal intubation, for example. These authors have listed therapeutic restriction opportunities with respect to respiratory care: 1) not initiate any measure in this regard; 2) not resort to orotracheal intubation; 3) restrict care procedure to tracheostomy if the patient has already been subjected to one; 4) restrict care to non-invasive procedures; or 5) initiate mechanical ventilation for a predetermined time period, at the end of which the patient shall have the tubes removed irrespective of having recovered or not.

Researchers3030. Garros D, Rosychuk RJ, Cox PN. Circumstances surrounding end of life in a pediatric intensive care unit. Pediatrics. 2003;112(5):e371.,3232. Geller G, Harrison KL, Rushton CH. Ethical challenges in the care of children and families affected by life-limiting neuromuscular diseases. J Dev Behav Pediatr. 2012;33(7):548-61.,4545. Levine DZ. Discontinuing immunosuppression in a child with a renal transplant: are there limits to withdrawing life support? Am J Kidney Dis. 2001;38(4):901-15. recognize that, clinically speaking, it is clearly futile when the organ that is being treated is failing despite the technological procedure that is being applied to it. In the case of mechanical ventilation within the context of terminal patient care, if the ventilation parameters are shown to be quite high over a long period and yet the clinical parameters denote respiratory insufficiency, then euthanasia becomes a non-issue regarding the suspension of mechanical ventilation procedures. On the contrary, therapeutic obstinacy clearly exists in maintaining the life of the patient who is on a razor's edge from which he will predictably fall, considering the indispensable invasive and painful treatment that he is undergoing.

Vose and Nelson7575. Vose LA, Nelson RM. Ethical issues surrounding limitation and withdrawal of support in the pediatric intensive care unit. J Intensive Care Med. 1999;14(5):220-30. believe that such a situation is representative of physiological futility, but that therapeutic futility may also refer to the entire clinical diagnosis of the patient when each form of advanced care is performed habitually, yet the condition of the patient is clearly deteriorating progressively, such as with patients that have neurodegenerative disorders. Frader and Michelson2727. Frader J, Michelson K. Can policy spoil compassion? Pediatr Crit Care Med. 2007;8(3):293-4. add that, in the context of terminally ill patients, if the patient must be deeply sedated in order to administer mechanical ventilation procedures, and not due to his clinical baseline condition, this is also a criterion that is an indicator of the existence of therapeutic obstinacy.

Respiratory care presents nuances in which it is not clear if only therapeutic restriction has been implemented or if the patient lost his life at that moment. Certain studies2323. Feltman D, Stokes T, Kett J, Lantos JD. Is treatment futile for an extremely premature infant with giant omphalocele? Pediatrics. 2014;133(1):123-8.,6969. Torres JCT, Goya JLH, Rubia NH, Jimenez PN, Munóz FG, Rodríguez JP et al. Recomendaciones sobre toma de decisiones y cuidados al final de la vida en neonatología. An Pediatr. 2013;78(1):190.e1-14.,7575. Vose LA, Nelson RM. Ethical issues surrounding limitation and withdrawal of support in the pediatric intensive care unit. J Intensive Care Med. 1999;14(5):220-30. describe the ethical prohibition of applying neuromuscular blocking agents during the removal of the patient's tubes, as obviously, if the diaphragm is paralyzed, death is brought about by the drug, not by the baseline illness. Regarding this issue, Morrison and Berkowitz5050. Morrison W, Berkowitz I. Do not attempt resuscitation orders in pediatrics. Pediatr Clin North Am. 2007;54(5):757-71., in addressing the need to distinguish between procedures, have determined that the term “euthanasia” may be used only when lethal medication is administered during the patient's intercritical periods. In other words, euthanasia as a practice would only be conducted during moments of clinical stability (that is, when there are no signs or symptoms of the illness worsening), and even so only when the patient has clearly expressed his wish to go through with the procedure. Alternatively, within contexts of emergency, the terminology that is most properly applied is “therapeutic restriction”.

Torres et al.6969. Torres JCT, Goya JLH, Rubia NH, Jimenez PN, Munóz FG, Rodríguez JP et al. Recomendaciones sobre toma de decisiones y cuidados al final de la vida en neonatología. An Pediatr. 2013;78(1):190.e1-14. elucidated that the removal of the patient's tubes, within the context of palliative care, must only occur after the patient has been off muscle relaxers, receives higher doses of sedatives or has had his ventilatory parameters decreased until the moment the tubes are removed and are substituted by some other less invasive respiratory care procedure, such as nasal oxygen cannulas. However, Penner et al.5454. Penner L, Cantor RM, Siegel L. Joseph's wishes: ethical decision-making in Duchenne muscular dystrophy. Mt Sinai J Med. 2010;77(4):392-7., upon studying a case of Duchenne muscular dystrophy, showed that it is not clear if mechanical ventilation within the patient's home via tracheostomy constitutes therapeutic obstinacy, or if it is simply a chronic form of care in the face of a severe and knowingly fatal disease.

In this sense, studies2323. Feltman D, Stokes T, Kett J, Lantos JD. Is treatment futile for an extremely premature infant with giant omphalocele? Pediatrics. 2014;133(1):123-8.,7777. Wilfond BS. Tracheostomies and assisted ventilation in children with profound disabilities: navigating family and professional values. Pediatrics. 2014;133(1 Suppl):S44-9. have shown that less invasive methods, such as tracheostomy or gastrostomy, are not, upon initial analysis, obstinate, but may in and of themselves require certain safeguards and generate other complications. The complications that are associated with these procedures may be indicative of the existence of therapeutic obstinacy. Similarly, the case of the patient that was described by Leeuwenburgh-Pronk et al.4343. Leeuwenburgh-Pronk WG, Miller-Smith L, Forman V, Lantos JD, Tibboel D, Buysse C. Are we allowed to discontinue medical treatment in this child? Pediatrics. 2015;135(3):545-9. shows how the distinction between therapeutic restrictions and euthanasia can be blurred: the patient's condition had been kept stable, albeit in critical condition, merely through the use of oxygen through the nose or via a catheter, which constitutes, in other words, non-invasive treatment, the removal of which, however, brought about death in a matter of a few hours.

The neuroethical issue is particularly important within the decision-making conflict regarding the suspension of respiratory care. In accordance with many authors1919. Devictor DJ, Latour JM. Forgoing life support: how the decision is made in European pediatric intensive care units. Intensive Care Med. 2011;37(11):1881-7.,2020. Diekema D, Botkin J. Clinical report: forgoing medically provided nutrition and hydration in children. Pediatrics. 2009;124(2):813-22.,2525. Feudtner C, Nathanson PG. Pediatric palliative care and pediatric medical ethics: opportunities and challenges. Pediatrics. 2014;133(1 Suppl):s1-7.,5555. Piva JP, Garcia PCR, Lago PM. Dilemas e dificuldades envolvendo decisões de final de vida e oferta de cuidados paliativos em pediatria. Rev Bras Ter Intensiva. 2011;23(1):78-86., in dealing with patients that suffer from severe cognitive sequelae (cerebral malformations, persistent coma, cerebral palsy, and so forth), doctors felt less discomfort in recommending the suspension and omission of treatment procedures than when dealing with non-oncological illnesses that do not affect the patient cognitively, such as neurodegenerative muscular disorders 2828. García-Salido A, Paso-Mora MG, Monleón-Luque M, Martino-Alba R. Palliative care in children with spinal muscular atrophy type I: what do they need? Palliat Support Care. 2015;13(2):313-7.,5454. Penner L, Cantor RM, Siegel L. Joseph's wishes: ethical decision-making in Duchenne muscular dystrophy. Mt Sinai J Med. 2010;77(4):392-7.,6767. Tan GH, Totapally BR, Torbati D, Wolfsdorf J. End-of-life decisions and palliative care in a children's hospital. J Palliat Med. 2006;9(2):332-42., cystic fibrosis4646. Liben S, Papadatou D, Wolfe J. Pediatric palliative care: challenges and emerging ideas. Lancet. 2008;371(9615):852-64., and pulmonary insufficiency due to hemosiderosis 3737. Hirani SA, Rahman A. Child with idiopathic pulmonary hemosiderosis: a case report from Pakistan with multiple ethical and moral issues. J Pediatr Nurs. 2012;27(4):e22-8. and so forth.

However, with respect to chromosomopathies and/or cerebral malformations, other studies 1212. Ambler J. When is the right time? Complex issues around withdrawing life-sustaining treatment in children. S Afr Med J. 2014;104(7):507-9.,7676. Wellesley H, Jenkins IA. Withholding and withdrawing life-sustaining treatment in children. Paediatr Anaesth. 2009;19(10):972-8. defend the position that the diagnosis in and of itself is not sufficient to recommend the implementation of therapeutic restrictions. This refers to diseases whose clinical manifestation may present varied intensities, from mild symptoms to severe complications that generate a situation in which the patient is dependent on life support technology. With certain frequency, patients that display these symptoms undergo periods of clinical stability. Feudtner2424. Feudtner C. Collaborative communication in pediatric palliative care: a foundation for problem-solving and decision-making. Pediatr Clin North Am. 2007;54(5):583-607. presents an illustration of the clinical condition, as a function of time, of such patients, in which one can note that the terminal nature of the condition becomes evident: 1) after the patient has been placed in an ICU, when his overall clinical condition will not return to its previous levels (stable discharge, however with sequelae); and 2) when the patient begins to suffer from severe, recurrent clinical complications.

With respect to nutrition or hydration via nasogastric probe or gastrostomy, in accordance with some authors1212. Ambler J. When is the right time? Complex issues around withdrawing life-sustaining treatment in children. S Afr Med J. 2014;104(7):507-9.,2020. Diekema D, Botkin J. Clinical report: forgoing medically provided nutrition and hydration in children. Pediatrics. 2009;124(2):813-22.,2626. Floriani C. Cuidados paliativos no domicílio: desafios aos cuidados de crianças dependentes de tecnologia. J Pediatr. 2010;86(1):15-20., nutrition only becomes a matter of essential care if the patient can demonstrate the capacity to swallow or if he is recovering that capacity. As a result, in cases where the patient is in a constant vegetative state, medical professionals in the UK and the United States allow the patient's guardians to make the decision. In other words, doctors will not recommend the suspension of such care; however, the process of feeding the patient via probe is suspended - while doses of sedatives are increased and the medical staff await death by dehydration - should the legally responsible parties so request it.

Leeuwenburgh-Pronk et al.4343. Leeuwenburgh-Pronk WG, Miller-Smith L, Forman V, Lantos JD, Tibboel D, Buysse C. Are we allowed to discontinue medical treatment in this child? Pediatrics. 2015;135(3):545-9. state that, generally speaking, the parents request suspension of the child's nutrition because the overall clinical condition of the care is too much of a burden, even though nutritional care in and of itself does not apparently cause any discomfort to the patient. Morrison and Kang5151. Morrison W, Kang T. Judging the quality of mercy: drawing a line between palliation and euthanasia. Pediatrics. 2014;133(1 Suppl):s31-6. state that feeding procedures may be suspended should they cause discomfort to the patient. Hidayat et al.3535. Hidayat T, Iqbal Z, Nasir A, Mohamad N, Taib F. Can I give food or drink to my terminally ill child? Education in Medicine Journal. 2015;7(3):e73-8. describe the case of a young girl with terminal cancer who felt very hungry and had a strong desire to eat, but suffered with involuntary vomiting that dehydrated her every time it occurred. Although such events are commonplace in the United States, according to Wellesley and Jenkins7676. Wellesley H, Jenkins IA. Withholding and withdrawing life-sustaining treatment in children. Paediatr Anaesth. 2009;19(10):972-8., at least half of American doctors do not agree that the suspension of artificial nutrition procedures is an ethically acceptable form of therapeutic restriction. Devictor and Latour1919. Devictor DJ, Latour JM. Forgoing life support: how the decision is made in European pediatric intensive care units. Intensive Care Med. 2011;37(11):1881-7. have shown that, in European countries, a tendency may exist to not initiate artificial nutrition procedures in specific cases, should the patient's guardians agree; however, the suspension of such procedures is rarely recommended.

Lastly, scholars2626. Floriani C. Cuidados paliativos no domicílio: desafios aos cuidados de crianças dependentes de tecnologia. J Pediatr. 2010;86(1):15-20.,7575. Vose LA, Nelson RM. Ethical issues surrounding limitation and withdrawal of support in the pediatric intensive care unit. J Intensive Care Med. 1999;14(5):220-30. emphasize that, with respect to the financial cost of treating terminal patients, it is not possible to affirm that the money that was not spent on a certain patient will necessarily be allocated to another patient that requires some form of treatment. Health care costs are monolithic; such that particular cases do not generate a significant financial impact on the system.

Final considertions

The therapeutic decision to initiate treatment or not, based on its double effect, is a debate that merges technical aspects with ethical issues, and should take into consideration the value of the patient's dignity as a human being. No treatment in and of itself is futile; the futility can be attributed to the relative value of that treatment, which is linked to the circumstances surrounding that type of treatment and the overall clinical context. In other words, the underlying issue is whether the possibility of a cure exists, or if the treatment is administered simply to provide relief to the patient66. Kipper DJ. O problema das decisões médicas envolvendo o fim da vida e propostas para nossa realidade. Bioética. 1999;7(1):59-70.. As such, the implementation of therapeutic restrictions is not a decision that should be made solely by a single health care professional, but by the entire team, for which the director is merely a spokesperson, in light of the fact that the legal responsibility that is involved is, above all else, institutional. Children that suffer from severe cerebral malformations most commonly suffer from terminal complications that are related to the respiratory apparatuses that they depend on, so that the most heated bioethical debate relates to not prescribing the use or suppression of mechanical ventilation.

Although therapeutic obstinacy is considered by society to be ethically questionable, current Brazilian law does not reflect this outlook. Laws exist that aim to restrict negligence, recklessness and euthanasia; however, no formal regulation or law exists to contravene excesses or the over medication of the terminally ill patient77. Academia Nacional de Cuidados Paliativos. Manual de cuidados paliativos. Rio de Janeiro: Diagraphic; 2009.. Notwithstanding, CFM Resolution 1.995/20128080. Conselho Federal de Medicina. Resolução CFM nº 1.995, de 31 de agosto de 2012. Dispõe sobre as diretivas antecipadas de vontade dos pacientes. Diário Oficial da União. Brasília, p. 269-270, 31 ago 2012. Seção 1., which concerns provisions regarding life expectancy, attempts to establish ethical-legal regulations that are extremely similar to those found in American culture, which are based on agreements and written decisions. This seems relatively strange to European culture, and perhaps also to that of Brazilians, both of which tend to adopt the stance of non-objection instead of favoring an agreement that was proposed by the patient himself.

From the ethical-legal point of view, currently, in Brazil, only medical staff have the authorization, in terms of palliative care, to restrict the use of diagnostic and therapeutic procedures. However, no judicial precedent exists that punishes the implementation of procedures that are characteristic of therapeutic obstinacy. To the contrary, acts of therapeutic obstinacy may be erroneously treated as the maintenance of the patient's right to live, in accordance with the Public Prosecutor's Office's dispute8181. Brasil. Seção Judiciária do Distrito Federal. 14ª. Vara Federal. Autos do processo 2007.34.00.014809-3. [acesso 11 out 2016]. Disponível: http://bit.ly/2efL5jy
http://bit.ly/2efL5jy...
against CFM Resolution 1.805/20068282. Conselho Federal de Medicina. Resolução CFM nº 1.805, de 28 de novembro de 2006. Na fase terminal de enfermidades graves e incuráveis é permitido ao médico limitar ou suspender procedimentos e tratamentos que prolonguem a vida do doente, garantindo-lhe os cuidados necessários para aliviar os sintomas que levam ao sofrimento, na perspectiva de uma assistência integral, respeitada a vontade do paciente ou de seu representante legal. Diário Oficial da União. Brasília. 28 nov 2006; seção 1: p.169.. In conclusion, patients that suffer from severe cerebral malformations are terminally ill, and are prescribed palliative care, which gives rise to the main ethical dilemma of whether or not to limit the patient's respiratory support. The decision of whether or not to limit certain efforts must be taken by the health care institution, by its medical staff, and the dialogue with the patient's parents or guardians represents one of the main ethical pillars that must be addressed in such situations. Most certainly, the indiscriminate use of advanced technology for patients in whichever clinical state is no longer ethically acceptable. Currently, the medical community is left to face the reality at hand and refine its practices in order to properly restrict the therapeutic procedures that terminal patients are subjected to.

Referências

  • 1
    Junges JR. Bioética: hermenêutica e casuística. São Paulo: Loyola; 2006.
  • 2
    Rodrigues CFA. Alteridade da morte de Emmanuel Levinas. Rev. bioét. (Impr.). 2012;20(3):442-50.
  • 3
    Taboada P. El derecho a morir con dignidad. Acta Bioeth. 2000;6(1):89-101.
  • 4
    Marreiro CL. Responsabilidade civil do médico na prática da distanásia. Rev. bioét. (Impr.). 2013;21(2):308-17.
  • 5
    Junges JR, Cremonese C, Oliveira EA, Souza LL, Backes V. Reflexões legais e éticas sobre o final da vida: uma discussão sobre a ortotanásia. Rev. bioét. (Impr.). 2010;18(2):275-88.
  • 6
    Kipper DJ. O problema das decisões médicas envolvendo o fim da vida e propostas para nossa realidade. Bioética. 1999;7(1):59-70.
  • 7
    Academia Nacional de Cuidados Paliativos. Manual de cuidados paliativos. Rio de Janeiro: Diagraphic; 2009.
  • 8
    Villas-Bôas ME. Da eutanásia ao prolongamento artificial. Rio de Janeiro: Forense; 2005.
  • 9
    Souza PVS. O médico e o dever legal de cuidar: algumas considerações jurídico-penais. Bioética. 2006;14(2):229-38.
  • 10
    Lien Foundation. The 2015 quality of death index: Ranking palliative care across the world. London: The Economist Intelligence Unit; 2015.
  • 11
    Marconi MA, Lakatos EM. Técnicas de pesquisa. 7ª ed. São Paulo: Atlas; 2012.
  • 12
    Ambler J. When is the right time? Complex issues around withdrawing life-sustaining treatment in children. S Afr Med J. 2014;104(7):507-9.
  • 13
    Basu RK. End-of-life care in pediatrics: ethics, controversies, and optimizing the quality of death. Pediatr Clin North Am. 2013;60(3):725-39.
  • 14
    Bovens L. Child euthanasia: should we just not talk about it? J Med Ethics. 2015;41(8):630-4.
  • 15
    Brook L, Hain R. Predicting death in children. Arch Dis Child. 2008;93:1067-70.
  • 16
    Cadell S, Ho G, Jacques L, Wilson K, Davies B, Steele R. Considerations for ethics in multisite research in pediatric palliative care. Palliat Med. 2009;23(3):274-5.
  • 17
    Clark J, Dudzinski D. The culture of dysthanasia: attempting CPR in terminally ill children. Pediatrics. 2013;131(3):572-80.
  • 18
    Colby WH, Dahlin C, Lantos J, Carney J, Christopher M. The National Consensus Project for Quality Palliative Care clinical practice guidelines domain 8: ethical and legal aspects of care. HEC Forum. 2010;22(2):117-31.
  • 19
    Devictor DJ, Latour JM. Forgoing life support: how the decision is made in European pediatric intensive care units. Intensive Care Med. 2011;37(11):1881-7.
  • 20
    Diekema D, Botkin J. Clinical report: forgoing medically provided nutrition and hydration in children. Pediatrics. 2009;124(2):813-22.
  • 21
    Durall A, Zurakowski D, Wolfe J. Barriers to conducting advance care discussions for children with life-threatening conditions. Pediatrics. 2012;129(4):e975-82.
  • 22
    Evans P, Saunders C. The management of fatal illness in childhood. Proc R Soc Med. 1969;62:15-7.
  • 23
    Feltman D, Stokes T, Kett J, Lantos JD. Is treatment futile for an extremely premature infant with giant omphalocele? Pediatrics. 2014;133(1):123-8.
  • 24
    Feudtner C. Collaborative communication in pediatric palliative care: a foundation for problem-solving and decision-making. Pediatr Clin North Am. 2007;54(5):583-607.
  • 25
    Feudtner C, Nathanson PG. Pediatric palliative care and pediatric medical ethics: opportunities and challenges. Pediatrics. 2014;133(1 Suppl):s1-7.
  • 26
    Floriani C. Cuidados paliativos no domicílio: desafios aos cuidados de crianças dependentes de tecnologia. J Pediatr. 2010;86(1):15-20.
  • 27
    Frader J, Michelson K. Can policy spoil compassion? Pediatr Crit Care Med. 2007;8(3):293-4.
  • 28
    García-Salido A, Paso-Mora MG, Monleón-Luque M, Martino-Alba R. Palliative care in children with spinal muscular atrophy type I: what do they need? Palliat Support Care. 2015;13(2):313-7.
  • 29
    Garros D. Uma “boa” morte em UTI pediátrica: é isso possível? J Ped. 2003;79(2 Suppl):S243-54.
  • 30
    Garros D, Rosychuk RJ, Cox PN. Circumstances surrounding end of life in a pediatric intensive care unit. Pediatrics. 2003;112(5):e371.
  • 31
    Gerhardt CA, Grollman JA, Baughcum AE, Young-Saleme T, Stefanik R, Klopfenstein KJ. Longitudinal evaluation of a pediatric palliative care educational workshop for oncology fellows. J Palliat Med. 2009;12(4):323-8.
  • 32
    Geller G, Harrison KL, Rushton CH. Ethical challenges in the care of children and families affected by life-limiting neuromuscular diseases. J Dev Behav Pediatr. 2012;33(7):548-61.
  • 33
    Gunn S, Hashimoto S, Karakozov M, Marx T, Tan IKS, Thompson DR et al Ethics roundtable debate: child with severe brain damage and an underlying brain tumour. Crit Care. 2004;8(4):213-8.
  • 34
    Ham C. Tragic choices in health care: lessons from the child B case. BMJ. 1999;319(7219):1258-61.
  • 35
    Hidayat T, Iqbal Z, Nasir A, Mohamad N, Taib F. Can I give food or drink to my terminally ill child? Education in Medicine Journal. 2015;7(3):e73-8.
  • 36
    Himelstein BP, Hilden JM, Boldt AM, Weissman D. Pediatric palliative care. N Engl J Med. 2004;350(17):1752-62.
  • 37
    Hirani SA, Rahman A. Child with idiopathic pulmonary hemosiderosis: a case report from Pakistan with multiple ethical and moral issues. J Pediatr Nurs. 2012;27(4):e22-8.
  • 38
    Hynson JL, Aroni R, Bauld C, Sawyer SM. Research with bereaved parents: a question of how not why. Palliat Med. 2006;20(8):805-11.
  • 39
    Jones BL, Contro N, Koch KD. The duty of the physician to care for the family in pediatric palliative care: context, communication, and caring. Pediatrics. 2014;133(1 Suppl):S8-15.
  • 40
    Kaczor C. Against euthanasia for children: a response to Bovens. J Med Ethics. 2016;42(1):57-8.
  • 41
    Klein SM. Moral distress in pediatric palliative care: a case study. J Pain Symptom Manage. 2009;38(1):157-60.
  • 42
    Lago P, Devictor D, Piva JP, Bergounioux J. Cuidados de final de vida em crianças: perspectivas no Brasil e no mundo. J Pediatr. 2007;83(2 Suppl):S109-15.
  • 43
    Leeuwenburgh-Pronk WG, Miller-Smith L, Forman V, Lantos JD, Tibboel D, Buysse C. Are we allowed to discontinue medical treatment in this child? Pediatrics. 2015;135(3):545-9.
  • 44
    Levetown M. Communicating with children and families: from everyday interactions to skill in conveying distressing information. Pediatrics. 2008;121(5):e1441-60.
  • 45
    Levine DZ. Discontinuing immunosuppression in a child with a renal transplant: are there limits to withdrawing life support? Am J Kidney Dis. 2001;38(4):901-15.
  • 46
    Liben S, Papadatou D, Wolfe J. Pediatric palliative care: challenges and emerging ideas. Lancet. 2008;371(9615):852-64.
  • 47
    Martin C. Deception and the death of Ilyusha: truth and the best interest of a dying child in The Brothers Karamazov. Pediatrics. 2014;134(2 Suppl):s87-96.
  • 48
    Mercurio MR, Murray PD, Gross I. Unilateral pediatric “do not attempt resuscitation” orders: the pros, the cons, and a proposed approach. Pediatrics. 2014;133(1 Suppl):S37-43.
  • 49
    Morgan D. Caring for dying children: assessing the needs of the pediatric palliative care nurse. Pediatr Nurs. 2009;35(2):86-90.
  • 50
    Morrison W, Berkowitz I. Do not attempt resuscitation orders in pediatrics. Pediatr Clin North Am. 2007;54(5):757-71.
  • 51
    Morrison W, Kang T. Judging the quality of mercy: drawing a line between palliation and euthanasia. Pediatrics. 2014;133(1 Suppl):s31-6.
  • 52
    Okhuysen-Cawley R, McPherson ML, Jefferson LS. Institutional policies on determination of medically inappropriate interventions: use in five pediatric patients. Pediatr Crit Care Med. 2007;8(3):225-30.
  • 53
    Pelant D, McCaffrey T, Beckel J. Development and implementation of a pediatric palliative care program. J Pediatr Nurs. 2012;27(4):394-401.
  • 54
    Penner L, Cantor RM, Siegel L. Joseph's wishes: ethical decision-making in Duchenne muscular dystrophy. Mt Sinai J Med. 2010;77(4):392-7.
  • 55
    Piva JP, Garcia PCR, Lago PM. Dilemas e dificuldades envolvendo decisões de final de vida e oferta de cuidados paliativos em pediatria. Rev Bras Ter Intensiva. 2011;23(1):78-86.
  • 56
    Powell R. Dilemmas in the medical treatment of patients facing inevitable death. Arch Dis Child. 2007;92(9):746-9.
  • 57
    Puckey M, Bush A. “Passage to paradise” ethics and end-of-life decisions in children. Paediatr Respir Rev. 2011;12(2):139-43.
  • 58
    Rahimzadeh V, Bartlett G, Longo C, Crimi L, Macdonald ME, Jabado N et al Promoting an ethic of engagement in pediatric palliative care research. BMC Palliat Care. 2015;14:50-7.
  • 59
    Ramnarayan P, Craig F, Petros A, Pierce C. Characteristics of deaths occurring in hospitalized children: changing trends. J Med Ethics. 2007;33(5):255-60.
  • 60
    Rapoport A, Shaheed J, Newman C, Rugg M, Steele R. Parental perceptions of forgoing artificial nutrition and hydration during end-of-life care. Pediatrics. 2013;131(5):861-9.
  • 61
    Renjilian CB, Womer JW, Carroll KW, Kang TI, Feudtner C. Parental explicit heuristics in decision-making for children with life-threatening illnesses. Pediatrics. 2013;131(2):e566-72.
  • 62
    Rezzónico CA. Bioética y derechos de los niños. Arch Argent Pediatr. 2004;102(3):214-9.
  • 63
    Ruppe MD, Feudtner C, Hexem KR, Morrison WE. Family factors affect clinician attitudes in pediatric end-of-life decision making: a randomized vignette study. J Pain Symptom Manage. 2013;45(5):832-40.
  • 64
    Sayeed SA. Baby doe redux? The Department of Health and Human Services and the Born-Alive Infants Protection Act of 2002: a cautionary note on normative neonatal practice. Pediatrics. 2005;116(4):e576-85.
  • 65
    Schildmann J, Hoetzel J, Baumann A, Mueller-Busch C, Vollmann J. Limitation of treatment at the end of life: an empirical-ethical analysis regarding the practices of physician members of the German Society for Palliative Medicine. J Med Ethics. 2011;37(6):327-32.
  • 66
    Siegel AM, Sisti DA, Caplan AL. Pediatric euthanasia in Belgium: disturbing developments. Jama. 2014;311(19):1963-4.
  • 67
    Tan GH, Totapally BR, Torbati D, Wolfsdorf J. End-of-life decisions and palliative care in a children's hospital. J Palliat Med. 2006;9(2):332-42.
  • 68
    Tomlinson D, Bartels U, Hendershot E, Constantin J, Wrathall G, Sung L. Challenges to participation in paediatric palliative care research: a review of the literature. Palliat Med. 2007;21(5):435-40.
  • 69
    Torres JCT, Goya JLH, Rubia NH, Jimenez PN, Munóz FG, Rodríguez JP et al Recomendaciones sobre toma de decisiones y cuidados al final de la vida en neonatología. An Pediatr. 2013;78(1):190.e1-14.
  • 70
    Truog RD, Meyer EC, Burns JP. Toward interventions to improve end-of-life care in the pediatric intensive care unit. Crit Care Med. 2006;34(11 Suppl):S373-9.
  • 71
    Tsai E. Withholding and withdrawing artificial nutrition and hydration. Paediatr Child Health. 2011;16(4):241-2.
  • 72
    Turner HN. Parental preference or child well-being: an ethical dilemma. J Pediatr Nurs. 2010;25(1):58-63.
  • 73
    Viallard ML. Some general considerations of a human-based medicine's palliative approach to the vulnerability of the multiply disabled child before the end of life. Cult Med Psychiatry. 2014;38(1):28-34.
  • 74
    Villares JM, Elízaga IV. Aspectos éticos en nutrición e hidratación en el niño: comentarios al documento de la Academia Americana de Pediatría. Acta Pediatr Esp. 2012;70(1):15-9.
  • 75
    Vose LA, Nelson RM. Ethical issues surrounding limitation and withdrawal of support in the pediatric intensive care unit. J Intensive Care Med. 1999;14(5):220-30.
  • 76
    Wellesley H, Jenkins IA. Withholding and withdrawing life-sustaining treatment in children. Paediatr Anaesth. 2009;19(10):972-8.
  • 77
    Wilfond BS. Tracheostomies and assisted ventilation in children with profound disabilities: navigating family and professional values. Pediatrics. 2014;133(1 Suppl):S44-9.
  • 78
    Zinner SE. The use of pediatric advance directives: a tool for palliative care physicians. Am J Hosp Palliat Care. 2008;25(6):427-30.
  • 79
    Silva FM, Nunes R. Caso belga de eutanásia em crianças: solução ou problema? Rev. bioét. (Impr.). 2015;23(3):475-84.
  • 80
    Conselho Federal de Medicina. Resolução CFM nº 1.995, de 31 de agosto de 2012. Dispõe sobre as diretivas antecipadas de vontade dos pacientes. Diário Oficial da União. Brasília, p. 269-270, 31 ago 2012. Seção 1.
  • 81
    Brasil. Seção Judiciária do Distrito Federal. 14ª. Vara Federal. Autos do processo 2007.34.00.014809-3. [acesso 11 out 2016]. Disponível: http://bit.ly/2efL5jy
    » http://bit.ly/2efL5jy
  • 82
    Conselho Federal de Medicina. Resolução CFM nº 1.805, de 28 de novembro de 2006. Na fase terminal de enfermidades graves e incuráveis é permitido ao médico limitar ou suspender procedimentos e tratamentos que prolonguem a vida do doente, garantindo-lhe os cuidados necessários para aliviar os sintomas que levam ao sofrimento, na perspectiva de uma assistência integral, respeitada a vontade do paciente ou de seu representante legal. Diário Oficial da União. Brasília. 28 nov 2006; seção 1: p.169.

Publication Dates

  • Publication in this collection
    2016

History

  • Received
    06 June 2016
  • Reviewed
    12 Oct 2016
  • Accepted
    17 Oct 2016
Conselho Federal de Medicina SGAS 915, lote 72, CEP 70390-150, Tel.: (55 61) 3445-5932, Fax: (55 61) 3346-7384 - Brasília - DF - Brazil
E-mail: bioetica@portalmedico.org.br