Acessibilidade / Reportar erro

MILITARY ETHICS: RETHINKING CIVIL-MILITARY RELATIONS IN BRAZIL

ÉTICA MILITAR: REPENSANDO AS RELAÇÕES CIVIL-MILITARES NO BRASIL

ABSTRACT

This paper presents a solid normative approach in military ethics, which justifies the rule of law in a constitutional regime capable of fixing the proper role of the Armed Forces in Brazil. Deploying this ethical framework, it analyzes the relevant literature, especially authors who defend civilian supremacy for the good functioning of a democratic society. Afterwards, some models of civil-military relations are introduced to establish the parameters and indicators of proper democratic consolidation. These parameters are applied to recent events, revealing that Brazil is regressing in its civilian control over the military. Finally, some practical proposals for reversing this tendency are put forward in pursuit of a fully democratic regime in Brazil.

Keywords:
Ethics; Civil-military relations; Democracy; Brazil

RESUMO

Este artigo apresenta um enfoque normativo sólido na ética militar capaz de justificar o Estado de Direito num regime constitucional que estabeleça a verdadeira função das Forças Armadas no Brasil. Aplicando esse referencial ético, o trabalho analisa a literatura relevante, especialmente autores que defendem a supremacia civil para o bom funcionamento de uma sociedade democrática. A seguir, alguns modelos nas relações civil-militares são introduzidos para estabelecer parâmetros e indicadores da consolidação democrática. Esses parâmetros são confrontados com fatos recentes mostrando que o Brasil está regredindo no controle civil sobre os militares. Finalmente, algumas propostas práticas para reverter essa tendência são apresentadas, buscando a consolidação de um regime democrático pleno.

Palavras-chave:
Ética; Relações civil-militares; Democracia; Brasil

Introduction

When the Brazilian Constitution of 1988 closed the book on more than 20 years of military dictatorship, it was widely believed that our country would finally enter an era of full democracy. It has become clear over the last decade (2011-20), however, that this transition was fragile and even incomplete. Recently, without a traditional coup d’état, the military has returned to political activities and regained positions of power. Representatives of the Armed Forces have held public offices in the last two federal administrations, in such vital departments as the Defense Ministry and many others. Does this mean that the military is outside civilian control and that Brazil remains a fragile democracy subject to a continued authoritarian menace?

In this paper, we propose a new military ethics for the Brazilian Armed Forces with the aim of preventing them from pursuing an undemocratic regime. We also identify the main factors that seem to authorize the military so frequently to break its compromise with liberal democratic values. To achieve this, in the first section we sort out the Triple Theory and the main tasks of military ethics in defining the institutionalized Armed Forces’ mission in a nation state governed by a constitutional regime. In the next section, building upon the proposed normative ethics (Triple Theory), we review that literature on civil-military relations which establishes the parameters and indicators for a truly democratic consolidation, with a special emphasis on Latin America in general and Brazil in particular. In the third section, we scrutinize some of the impediments to a full transition to democracy in Brazil. We also argue for a new normativity in civil-military relations in our country, as recent events show that the Brazilian Armed Forces do not respect the main role of the military in a liberal democratic regime. In the final remarks, we show that democracy is in the country’s best interest and good for both the military institution and for civilians.

The main proposal of this work is to contribute to an acknowledgement that a complete transition to a fully democratic regime demands civilian control of the military, and that the latter should only hold roles to address external threats. This has been subject to recent debate in Brazil. Diniz and Rocha (2021)DINIZ, E., ROCHA, A. “Ir além da PEC Pazuello”. Valor Econômico. 23 August 2021. https://valor.globo.com/opiniao/coluna/ir-alem-da-pec-pazuello.ghtml (Accessed on: 13/10/21).
https://valor.globo.com/opiniao/coluna/i...
, for example, argue that a return of the military to the barracks is both economically and politically desirable. The continued involvement of active military personnel in civilian affairs has demonstrated repeatedly that they are not qualified to perform fundamental governmental roles. For example, General Pazuello’s performance as Health Minister was disastrous, and so was General Braga Neto’s security intervention in Rio de Janeiro—as General Villas Bôas has acknowledged (Castro, 2021, p. 211CASTRO, C. “General Villas Bôas: Conversa com o Comandante”. Rio de Janeiro: FGV Editora, 2021.). Therefore, the study of civil-military relations, from a normative ethical and political approach, contributes to the literature in the field since it brings together the study of ethics and of political science. Finally, the main proposals in our concluding remarks are an urgent matter for Brazil’s democracy.

1. What is Military Ethics?

Before trying to stipulate a clear definition of military ethics and its main theoretical tasks, it is crucial to understand ethics itself and distinguish it from morality. For the purposes of this work, ethics is conceived in broad terms as the philosophic-scientific study of moral phenomena. According to some authors, for example, Borges et al. (2002)BORGES, M. L., DALL’AGNOL, D., DUTRA, D.V. «Ética». Rio de Janeiro: DP&A, 2002., it comprises three main spheres: (i) metaethical problems (e.g., whether there is objective moral knowledge or whether judgements are just subjective); (ii) normative issues (for instance, whether utility, rights or character is the standard by which to judge the correctness of actions, leading to consequentialism, deontology or virtue ethics) and (iii) applied questions such as whether a particular war is just or not. As we can see, military ethics is a domain of applied ethics as are many other areas such as medical ethics and environmental ethics, each of which discusses practical problems related to special subjects. To be more specific, military ethics may, among other things, examine the conditions of war not only in its economic and political aspects, but also in the permissibility of deploying force that leads to violent events and deaths.

In this work, we will assume a cognitivist and realist metaethics and apply a normative ethical approach based on Parfit’s Triple Theory, which combines elements of consequentialism and deontology, to scrutinize some issues in civil-military relations. Despite the fact that it goes beyond the limits of this work to sort out in a detailed way this normative approach, it is worth clarifying some of its main principles. In the first volume of On What Matters (2013, p. 411), the author reinterprets three well-known ethical theories in order to achieve normative convergence. To state briefly, they are:

  • i) Rule Consequentialism: Everyone ought to follow the principles that are optimific;

  • ii) the Kantian Formula: Everyone ought to follow the principles whose universal acceptance everyone could rationally will;

  • iii) Scanlon’s Contractualism: An act is wrong if it would be disallowed by any principle that no one could reasonably reject.

Basically, then, the Triple Theory states that an “act is wrong just when such acts are disallowed by the principles that are optimific, uniquely universally willable, and not reasonably rejectable” (Parfit, 2013, p. 413PARFIT, D. “On What Matters”. (2v.) Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013.). Thus, according to Parfit, both Kantianism and contractualism are deontological theories, which are compatible with rule consequentialism, leading to this fundamental ethical metaprinciple.

It might be objected that the Triple Theory would be received with some skepticism by traditional Kantians and Utilitarians. This may well be true, but one must also bear in mind that not all theories are fully taken on board (act consequentialism or Kant’s own ethics are not accepted) and that Parfit is mainly reinterpreting ethical theories in order to achieve congruence. In fact, the second volume of On What Matters contains commentaries by Susan Wolf, Allen Wood, Barbara Herman and T. M. Scanlon, and Parfit’s answers to them. We believe Parfit made a substantial contribution to normative ethics (see also Singer, 2017SINGER, P. (ed.). “Does Anything Really Matter? Essays on Parfit on Objectivity”. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017., for further discussions). As Parfit argues (2013PARFIT, D. “On What Matters”. (2v.) Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013., p.419), “It has been widely believed that there are such deep disagreements between Kantians, Contractualists, and Consequentialists. That, I have argued, is not true. These people are climbing the same mountain on different sides.” We cannot fully reconstruct this debate here since we are more interested in applying it to a subfield of practical ethics. One way of recognizing the Triple Theory’s cogency is testing it against our ordinary moral beliefs. By the way, Parfit himself made some applications holding that rich people should give up some luxuries, ceasing to overheat the Earth’s atmosphere, and taking care of our planet so it continues to support life (Parfit, 2013, p. 419PARFIT, D. “On What Matters”. (2v.) Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013.). Thus, we will deploy Parfit’s Triple Theory, in this and the next section, to present a solid approach in military ethics. Later, we will use the above metaprinciple to justify our specific proposals for a full transition towards democracy in Brazil. Before doing that, let us better clarify what military ethics is all about.

To better understand the role of military ethics and most issues it deals with, we can use the “just war theory,” which provides a good illustration of some moral problems in this field. Just war was discussed in Greek (Aristotle) and Roman (Cicero) antiquity, through medieval (Augustine and Aquinas) and modern times (Locke, Kant etc.), and up to our contemporary age, especially post World War II, as exemplified by Walzer’s (2000)WALZER, M. “Just and Unjust Wars. A Moral Argument with Historical Illustrations”. New York: Basic Books, 2000. seminal work Just and Unjust Wars (see references). Usually, a just war theory deals with three main issues: (i) it asks in which circumstances and to what aims is organized military force justified (jus ad bellum)? This may include examining the raison d’être of the military itself, for instance, whether it is for the protection of a nation’s borders only or may have other internal roles; (ii) just war theory also asks what are the norms that govern military action in war (jus in bello)? For example, the Geneva Convention forbids the killing of civilians; finally, (iii) just war theory deals with the complexity of post war issues (Jus Post Bellum), for instance, the military’s role in reconstruction, peacekeeping, civilian security, and upholding human rights and democracy. Different answers to these questions give rise to a range of views extending from pacifism (force and violence are never justified) to radical realism, as expressed in the saying “all is fair in love and war,” and more nuanced forms of pragmatism. These issues also lead to different models for discussing civil-military relations: liberal, corporatist, militarist, or neopatrimonialist political culture (Mares, 1998, p. 4MARES, D. R. (ed.). “Civil-Military Relations. Building Democracy and Regional Security in Latin America, Southern Asia, and Central Europe”. New York/London: Routledge, 1998.). We will discuss some of these models in the next section, but it is clear that military ethics involves many empirical issues as well as normative ones. We are especially interested here in how civil-military relations ought to be, not only how they are currently conducted in Brazil. Irrespective of the best model the Triple Theory can justify, we can at least agree that military ethics is a branch of applied normative ethics.

Bearing this ethical scheme in mind (metaethics, normative and applied ethics), and the military questions involved in classical war issues, we are now in a position to postulate not only a clear definition of military ethics, but also to sort out its main problems and theoretical tasks. According to, for example, Baumann (2007, p. 35)BAUMANN, D. “Military Ethics: a Task for Armies”. Military Medicine. Vol. 172, Nr. suppl_2, November 2007, pp. 34-38. https://doi.org/10.7205/MILMED.173.Supplement_2.34 (Accessed on: 16/09/21).
https://doi.org/10.7205/MILMED.173.Suppl...
, the definition of military ethics can be made in these terms:

Military ethics judges and justifies military actions from a moral point of view. It defines standards of good behavior for individual military personnel (as individuals and/or members of a group) and develops these standards. It asks critical questions of existing laws and regulations in connection with organized military force and seeks to change these laws, if necessary, within the framework of the democratic process.

Military ethics comprises, then, both moral standards for judging personnel’s behavior and institutional issues concerning the role of the armies within a democratic regime. In this work, we will not deal with questions related to individual soldiers’ actions. A soldier’s behavior is a problem for “professional military ethics;” that is, the personal qualities (character, virtues) necessary to be a good soldier. This depends on many circumstances and may include specific rules of behavior, values and military training. These issues can, just to illustrate, be found in the Military Statute (as adopted by, for instance, AMAN [Academia Militar de Agulhas NegrasACADEMIA MILITAR DAS AGULHAS NEGRAS. (http://www.aman.eb.mil.br/)
http://www.aman.eb.mil.br/...
]), which specifies rules for discipline and obedience as well as values such as honor. Rather, we are here more concerned with other problems, namely, “institutional military ethics.” According to Baumann (2007, p. 36)BAUMANN, D. “Military Ethics: a Task for Armies”. Military Medicine. Vol. 172, Nr. suppl_2, November 2007, pp. 34-38. https://doi.org/10.7205/MILMED.173.Supplement_2.34 (Accessed on: 16/09/21).
https://doi.org/10.7205/MILMED.173.Suppl...
, “Military ethics, as applied ethics, has as the most important points of reference constitutional law honoring international law and the Law of Armed Conflict (should level) and the conscience of the individual soldier (want level).” Consequently, we will focus only on the institutional aspects of the Brazilian Armed Forces in relation to their justifiable constitutional role within a democratic regime. This must establish their mission, structure and budget under, as we will see, civilian control.

The set of moral issues that therefore interests us in this work has to do with the second statement in Baumann’s characterization of military ethics quoted above; that is, critical questions regarding existing regulations of organized military force that could contribute to changing these laws if necessary within the framework of the democratic process. This gives rise to the problem of civil-military relations in their institutional framework. For instance, how can we assure the primacy of civilian authority and the political neutrality of the military? That is to say, we are concerned with the constitutional role of the Armed Forces in a democratic regime.

It is first necessary to clarify that by using the Triple Theory, the most basic constitutional assumption in the civil-military relations debate is the acceptance of the rule of law in a democratic state in defining the role of the Armed Forces. That is to say, the rule of law is optimific, universally willable and would not be rejected by a reasonable person. Now, the idea of the rule of law can be traced back to Aristotle (1287a21)ARISTOTLE. “Politics”. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995.: “The rule of law is preferable … to that of a single citizen” since individuals are subject to passions, and rulers “… should be made ‘law-guardians’ or ‘servants’ of the law.” These ideas lead to the law-governed state ideal (in German, Rechststaat; in French, État de droit; in Portuguese, Estado Democrático de Direito). As has been established since modern times, a republican state avoids absolutism (authoritarian regimes) by dividing political power into three main branches: the legislative, judiciary and executive (see Locke, 1994, p. 364LOCKE, J. “Two Treatises of Government”. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994.). There are no other legitime political powers in a democratic regime guided by the rule of law. A republic must seek the right balance between these powers. According to Kant (8: 352), republicanism is simply the political idea of division of power to avoid authoritarian and despotic regimes.

The question becomes, then, what characterizes the rule of law within a democratic republic? Roughly speaking, and following Gingham’s excellent work (2011, p.8), we may state that the rule of law is the constitutional principle which asserts that all persons must be governed by a fair system of public rules that specify rights and obligations establishing the elements of the common good, are enacted by a competent legislative authority, are democratically voted for by all citizens, and applied in litigating cases by impartial judges in fair trials. If one then asks “how can it be justified?” the Triple Theory can be used to show that following the constitutional principle is optimific and is therefore universally desirable. This juridico-political principle, as we will see below, amounts to the idea of autonomy or self-rule, which is arguably the most basic premise of modern democracies.

To establish the role of the Armed Forces under this constitutional principle, we need to set out in more detail some tenets of a democratic regime. Before doing that, however, let us ask: what makes democracy so valuable that is it considered the best form of government? According to some authors (e.g., Graham, 1986GRAHAM, K. “The Battle of Democracy. Conflict, Consensus and the Individual”. Brighton: Wheatsheaf Books, 1986.), democracy should be favoured both for its consequences and for its intrinsic properties. We support this view, since democracy allows persons to pursue their own interests (non-moral consequences) as well as justice and liberty (moral consequences), and it involves treating people with the proper respect to which they are entitled. Again, we can appeal to the Triple Theory to justify the moral component of a democratic regime: it is optimific, universally willable and would not be rejected by a reasonable person. This means that democracy is valuable both in itself and for its results, making it the best form of government from both a deontological and consequentialist perspective. That is, democracy in any form (direct, participatory, representative etc.) is the political materialization of autonomy or of a person’s self-rule. Unfortunately, exploring the different types of democratic regime goes beyond the limits of this study (on this point, see: Gutmann, 1995GUTMANN, A. “Democracy”. In: GOODIN, R. E., PETTIT, P. A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell, 1995. pp. 411-421).

Democracy is sometimes conflated with majority rule only or other common-sense beliefs such as the government “of the people, by the people, and for the people”. This is not the whole truth. Actually, a democratic regime comprises several complex institutional arrangements beyond the above-mentioned division of power. According to Dahl (1998)DAHL, R. “On Democracy”. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1998., a real democratic regime must also consist of: (i) elected public officials; (ii) free, fair and frequent elections; (iii) freedom of expression: (iv) alternative sources of information; (v) associational autonomy, and (vi) a sense of inclusive citizenship. These institutions are crucial in judging whether a particular state has a truly democratic regime or is moving in the direction of democratic consolidation. Democracy in Brazil is still very fragile indeed, and the system of checks and balances does not always work properly. One indicator that we need to do more to achieve democratic consolidation is that the Defense Ministry is, at the time of writing (October 2021), exclusively controlled by the military. And some believe that this gives the forces a special power to moderate and mediate the relationships between executive, legislative and judiciary. We will return to this point in the next two sections.

Among the fundamental values of democracy (interests, liberties etc.) equality is paramount in understanding civil-military relations. Most contemporary political philosophers and ethicists alike argue that, from a moral point of view, all people are equal (Rawls, 1999RAWLS, J. “A Theory of Justice”. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999.; Dworkin, 2005DWORKIN, R. “Levando os Direitos a Sério”. São Paulo: Martins Fontes, 2005.). That is to say, everyone has the same moral rights and responsibilities, and this can, again, be justified by the Triple Theory. Thus, political equality (for instance, as stated in the rule “one person, one vote”) is based on moral personality, especially the idea that persons are free and equal beings no matter their civic condition. A truly democratic regime depends on the moral equality of individuals whatever their status: civilian or military. Unfortunately, militarism denies this fundamental democratic value with no proper moral justification. Therefore, it is only under a democratic regime that civil control of the Armed Forces guarantees moral equality independently of a person’s civilian or military public role.

We can now recognize that from the rule of law and the main moral assumptions of a democratic regime, the best model of state-society relations in establishing the role of the military is, in Mares’ terms, “the liberal one” (1998, p. 4)MARES, D. R. (ed.). “Civil-Military Relations. Building Democracy and Regional Security in Latin America, Southern Asia, and Central Europe”. New York/London: Routledge, 1998.. As we will see in the next section, in this model (‘liberal’ in the political, not economical sense), the basis of sovereignty is the people; consequently, the military must be subordinated to civilian control. The corporatist, militarist or neopatrimonialist models invert the people–government relationship, leading to a fundamental moral distortion since society is dominated by the military. These models break the rule of law and fundamental democratic values such as moral equality.

Having set out the main problems and theoretical tasks of military ethics, let us now analyze more specifically some issues related to civil-military relations. As we will show, Brazil has a bad historical record concerning respect for democratic values and the rule of law, and the military have frequently been involved in implementing dictatorial regimes.

2. Some normative issues in civil-military relations

Bearing the previous section in mind, growing scholarly concern has prompted the development of a civil-military relations subfield that deals with some important normative issues. It is beyond the limits of this work to present all the questions this field deals with (For good appraisals, see: Croissant, Kuehn, 2017CROISSANT, A., KUEHN (eds.). “Reforming Civil-Military Relations in New Democracies: Democratic Control and Military Effectiveness in Comparative Perspectives”. Chame: Springer, 2017.; Bruneau, Matei, 2013BRUNEAU, T. C., MATEI, F. C., (eds.). “The Routledge Handbook of Civil-Military Relations”. New York: Routledge, 2013.; Feaver, 2017FEAVER, P. “Civil-Military Relations and Policy: A Sampling of a New Wave of Scholarship”. Journal of Strategic Studies, 40 (1-2), pp. 325-342, 2017.; Brooks, 2019BROOKS, R. A. “Integrating the Civil-Military Relations Subfield”. Annu. Rev. Political Sci. Vol. 1, pp. 379-398, 2019.); it is, however, worth briefly pointing out some of its main topics and developments so we can establish the normative aspects of military duties in a democratic society. Existing theoretical frameworks are important since they elaborate the parameters of analysis, conceptual contributions and typologies which will reinforce our contention that Brazil’s civil-military relations have regressed over the last decade. This section therefore resumes the previous topic of military ethics. It does so to lay the foundations for the final section, in which we make some normative and other practical recommendations to reorganize Brazilian civil-military relations.

Let us begin by recalling a classic distinction in this area. Samuel Huntington’s (1957)HUNTINGTON, S. P. “The Soldier and the State: The Theory and Politics of Civil-Military Relations”. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Univ. Press, 1957. seminal “The Solider and the State” established a model for distinguishing civilian “subjective control,” in which the military is subordinate to a specific group in power; and “objective” control, in which subordination exists no matter who holds office. Objective control generates military effectiveness and apolitical professionalism. Scholars of civil-military relations are interested in evaluating progress in terms of “objective” control, and they assume that democracy is the best form of government (Mares, 2014MARES, D. R., MARTÍNEZ, R. (eds.). “Debating Civil-Military Relations in Latin America”. Brighton: Sussex Academic Press, 2014.), an idea that, as mentioned above, we support.

An apparent paradox intrinsic to this debate is what Feaver (1999)FEAVER, P.. “Civil-Military Relations”. Annual Review of Political Science, Vol. 2, pp. 211-241, June 1999. calls the civil-military “problematique”. On the one hand, the military is a regime and the State’s chief protector. On the other, the military is an actor which can turn its guns on the government and remove leaders, making it a source of insecurity and threat. From Huntington’s typologies to Feaver’s paradox, the study of civil-military relations involves a range of topics, including the relationship between the military and wider society, the military and other government actors, and between leaders and organizations within the military (Nielsen, Snider, 2009, p. 3NIELSEN S. C., SNIDER D. M. (eds.). “American Civil-Military Relations: The Soldier and the State in a New Era”. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins Univ. Press, 2009.).

Given the many historical and current examples, military coups d’état have been a primary concern of scholars in the field (Gassebner et al., 2016GASSEBNER, M., GUTMAN, J., VOIGT, S. “When to expect a coup d’état? An extreme bounds analysis of coup determinants”. Public Choice, 169(3), pp. 293-31, 2016.; Thompson, 1973THOMPSON, W. R. “Grievances of Military Coup-Makers”. Beverly Hills, CA: Sage, 1973.; Nordlinger, 1977NORDLINGER, E. A. “Soldiers in Politics: Military Coups and Governments”. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1977.; Belkin, Schofer, 2003BELKIN, A., SCHOFER E. “Toward a structural understanding of coup risk”. J. Confl. Resolut., 47(5), pp. 594-620, 2003.; Powell, 2012POWELL, J. M. “Determinants of the attempting and outcome of coups d’état”. J. Confl. Resolut. 56(6), pp. 1017-1040, 2012.; Böhmelt, Pilster, 2015BÖHMELT, T., PILSTER, U. “The impact of institutional coup-proofing on coup attempts and coup outcomes”. Int. Interact., 41, pp. 158-82, 2015.; De Bruin, 2018DE BRUIN, E. “Preventing coups d’état: how counterbalancing works”. J. Confl. Resolut., 62(7), pp. 1-26, 2018.). Preventing these coups, explaining their origins, and—especially important to Latin America in general and to Brazil—consolidating a truly democratic society where the military is subordinated to civilian rule is the strand in which our article is embedded. The variables and parameters that allow an analyst to determine which norms and institutions must change and how we can verify these changes pose the following question: what indicators of democratic consolidation are we looking for? (Martínez, 2014MARTÍNEZ, R. “Objectives for Democratic Consolidation in the Armed Forces”. In: MARES, D. R., MARTÍNEZ, R. Debating Civil-Military Relations in Latin America. Brighton: Sussex Academic Press, 2014. pp. 21-60.).

This is the question of civilian control, and it is arguably the most important in military ethics in general and the subfield of civil-military relations in particular. Even in a “formal democratic” constitutional and institutional situation, the military can wield an extraordinary amount of political power through several sources. Political scientists, especially bureaucratic theorists, expect bureaus and institutions to maximize their budget, prestige, and monopoly over their role (Allison, 1969ALLISON, G. T. “Essence of Decision: Explaining the Cuban Missile Crisis”. Boston: Little, Brown, 1969.; Allison, Halperin, 1972ALLISON, G. T., HALPERIN, M. H. “Bureaucratic Politics: A Paradigm and Some Policy Implications”. World Politics. Nr. 24, p. 40–79, 1972.). This, together with the historical role of the military in Brazil and their self-perception as the true representatives of the people’s will, means it is even more important to act urgently to create solid instruments for civilian oversight and control. The military, as a powerful bureaucratic actor, manages large budgets, privileged information and specific missions which can influence governability. Like other bureaucratic actors, they fight for their own interests, and to do so they coalesce with civilian constituencies and other political actors (Fordham, 2001FORDHAM, B. O. “Military Interests and Civilian Politics: The Influence of the Civil Military ‘Gap’ on Peacetime Military Policy”. In: FEAVER, P., KOHN, R. (eds.). Soldiers and Civilians: The Civil-Military Gap and American National Security. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2001. pp. 355-85.). The military can contest civilian authority via informal means (Stepan, 1973STEPAN. “The new professionalism of internal warfare and military role expansion”. In: STEPAN, A. (ed.) Authoritarian Brazil: Origins, Politics and Future. New Haven, CT: Yale Univ. Press, 1973. pp. 47-69.; Pion-Berlin, 1997PION-BERLIN, D. “Through Corridors of Power: Institutions and Civil–Military Relations in Argentina”. University Park, PA: Pa. State Univ. Press, 1997.). The degree of civilian control depends on the allocation of prerogatives, civilian bureaus’ institutional capacity, and the entities in charge of overseeing military activity (Bruneau, Tollefson, 2006BRUNEAU, T. D., TOLLEFSON, S. D. (eds.). “Who Guards the Guardians and How: Democratic Civil--Military Relations”. Austin, TX: Univ. Texas Press, 2006.).

Given the importance of these issues, scholars have elaborated indicators and frameworks to evaluate the consolidation of civilian rule in democracies (Mares, Martínez, 2014MARES, D. R., MARTÍNEZ, R. (eds.). “Debating Civil-Military Relations in Latin America”. Brighton: Sussex Academic Press, 2014.; Albright, 1980ALBRIGHT, D. E. “A Comparative Conceptualization of Civil-Military Relations”. World Politics. Nr. 32, pp. 553-576, 1980.; Perlmutter; 1969PERLMUTTER, A. “The Praetorian State and the Praetorian Army: Towards a Taxonomy of Civil Military Relations in Developing Polities”. Comparative Politics, Vol. 1, Nr. 3, pp. 382-404, 1969.). Authors generally agree about the main factors necessary for democratic consolidation (Mares, Martínez, 2014MARES, D. R., MARTÍNEZ, R. (eds.). “Debating Civil-Military Relations in Latin America”. Brighton: Sussex Academic Press, 2014.): i) legislative modification and withdrawal of the military from all branches of civil administration; ii) a solid, civil-led defense ministry with strong civilian oversight; iii) demarcation of the proper role of the military as defense of the country against external threats, and iv) parliamentary control of security and defense policy, among others. We can justify these elements with the Triple Theory, and this will lead to democratic and civilian control of the military.

We can now state more clearly the main mission of the legitime Armed Forces (military). This issue is crucial since many argue that the military must have a role only in national defense against external forces (e.g., to protect borders and to kill enemies if needed) or in the UN’s peacekeeping forces. Given the results of the previous section, we support this view based on the liberal model against militarism and other alternatives. To better understand the differences between them, we would like to spell out Mares’ framework for an analysis of the civil-military relations underlying the role of the military:

  • i) Liberal political culture: the basis of sovereignty is the people; the government is subordinated to the people; the military is part of the governmental apparatus, and as such, it is subordinated to the will of the people via the civilian government;

  • ii) Organic corporativist political culture: the basis of sovereignty is inherent to the state and the government is dominant; military participation in politics is facilitated by constitutional clauses that permit fairly easy declarations of states of emergency;

  • iii) Militarist political culture: the basis of sovereignty is inherent to the state and the government is dominant; the military is the repository of the national vision, and there are historical moments in which it has the moral obligation to assume leadership;

  • iv) Neopatrimonial political culture: the basis of sovereignty is inherent to the state and the government is dominant; the military is perceived as one more group of elites who wish to gain favor with the leader and whom the leader wishes to include in his coalition (cf. Mares, 1998, pp. 3-5MARES, D. R. (ed.). “Civil-Military Relations. Building Democracy and Regional Security in Latin America, Southern Asia, and Central Europe”. New York/London: Routledge, 1998.).

In the model we are defending here, the military is subordinated to civil control and is responsible for national defense against external threats only. As we anticipated, the corporatist, militarist or neopatrimonialist models invert the people–government relationship, leading to a fundamental moral distortion since society is easily dominated by the military.

The question becomes, according to Lee (2012, p. 290)LEE, S. “Ethics and Democracy. An Introduction”. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012.: “what is a state permitted to do through the use of military force to those outside its borders?” As we saw above, just war theory provides classical answers. Now, as we will see in more detail in the next section, one of the main problems in Brazil (and in Latin America in general where democracy remains fragile) is that the legislation prescribes the military other internal roles, for instance, law and order maintenance (so-called LOGOS “Law and Order Guarantee Operations”). Apart from being ineffective, as the recent Rio de Janeiro intervention showed, this leads to many other problems, such as the killing of innocent civilians, since the military do not have proper training in securing internal stability. To put it in Mares’ terms (2018, p. 5), “in Argentina and, to a lesser degree, Brazil, the civil-rights horrors and economic disasters of the bureaucratic-authoritarian governments of the 1970s and 1980s fundamentally changed each country’s political culture by delegitimizing military rule and state power.” The military are trained for combat in legitimate wars, which implies a depersonalization of the external enemy and the use of lethal force if necessary. That is why the military cannot be used to secure internal order. To achieve stable internal order, the civil police seems to be a better fit. We will return to this point in the third section.

We need, however, more specific criteria to recognize the dysfunctionality of the military when they fail to keep to their proper role and jeopardize democratic regimes. Martínez (2014, pp. 23-24.)MARTÍNEZ, R. “Objectives for Democratic Consolidation in the Armed Forces”. In: MARES, D. R., MARTÍNEZ, R. Debating Civil-Military Relations in Latin America. Brighton: Sussex Academic Press, 2014. pp. 21-60. has created a framework including a series of indicators with the aim of analyzing the consolidation of democracy in the Armed Forces. The author divides these indicators into four main spheres i) civil supremacy; ii) military neutrality; iii) “civilianization of the military,” and iv) civil culture. It is important to point out that if all these indicators are accomplished, a fully democratic liberal society will emerge. However, bargaining, conflict, and profound modifications to government, the military and civil society would be necessary to achieve the author’s full range of proposals, making it a difficult task. Nevertheless, the completeness and highly detailed nature of Martinez’s model make it a good starting point for an evaluation of democratic consolidation. As will become clear in the next section, Brazil has, especially over the last decade, regressed in all these indicators towards a less democratic society. Martínez’s framework and indicators are presented in Table 1.

Table 1
Consolidation of a Military Administration under a Democratic Regime

This paper does not aim to cover all Martínez’s parameters and indicators for a truly civil-military democratic consolidation. But recent developments in Brazil demonstrate that in many ways—most ways—the country is on a path away from true civil rule and therefore democracy. The Brazilian military’s perception of its role as a “moderator power” and as having the right to engage in “law and order maintenance” is influenced by a number of factors, including what some sectors of society sometimes ask of it. To be a moderator power is, however, not their constitutional attribution, going against the most basic democratic principles. Furthermore, a lack of civilian control over operations and accountability, and the lack of a clearly established role for the military, create a serious problem for the goal of civilian rule. The military and its supporters can inappropriately extend their institutional autonomy “into realms that make it difficult for civilian governments to remain in control” (Mares; Martinez, 2014, p. 212MARES, D. R., MARTÍNEZ, R. (eds.). “Debating Civil-Military Relations in Latin America”. Brighton: Sussex Academic Press, 2014.). In Latin America, the military expanded to have missions in both external and internal defense, as is clear in Brazil’s case. As Mares & Martinez (2014, p. 215)MARES, D. R., MARTÍNEZ, R. (eds.). “Debating Civil-Military Relations in Latin America”. Brighton: Sussex Academic Press, 2014. states:

Latin America still has not solved the puzzle of civil-military relations […] Indicators show those democratic institutions are not strong and thus militaries do not face as severe constraints on transforming their domestic roles into political authority in crisis periods as many have assumed.

Brazil’s path towards a healthy civil-military balance and the consolidation of civilian rule and democracy is not straightforward, and many authors have pointed out the distortions in its constitutional and political system, such as prerogatives still in place from the most recent military dictatorship.

We now turn to the recent regression in civil–military relations in Brazil. In the previous section, we showed how military ethics helps to ground civilian control of the Armed Forces in a democratic regime. This section then briefly outlined the parameters, indicators and resultant political actions for the consolidation of democracy, as well as some challenges to this. Next, we analyze some Brazilian idiosyncrasies and the specific steps necessary to move towards civilian rule. This analysis allows us to generate some concrete proposals given the reality in the country.

3. Brazil: The civil-military question as an urgent matter for democracy

Keeping in mind the main results of the two previous sections, namely the way military ethics based on the Triple Theory helps to better ground civil-military relations in a constitutional regime under the rule of law, in this part we examine why Brazil must change if it is to achieve true democracy: this is optimific, universally willable and would not be rejected by a reasonable person. As we will see, the most recent transition to democracy did not guarantee the necessary instruments for civilian supremacy in government, whether in developing defense policy or supervising the actions of the Armed Forces. As touched on above, the promulgation of the 1988 constitution maintained most of the military’s prerogatives and privileges, with a large margin of autonomy from the Brazilian political system (Soares, 2019SOARES, S. A. “Da Constituinte à Comissão Nacional da Verdade: A Questão Militar como Entrave Perene ao Estado de Direito e à Democracia no Brasil”. Perseu, Vol. 13, Nr. 18, pp. 151-165, 2019.; Saint-Pierre, 2002SAINT-PIERRE, H. L. “Formas não-golpistas de presença militar no estado”. Perspectivas (24-5), São Paulo, pp. 115-130, 2002.; Montero, 2014MONTERO, A. P. “Brazil: Reversal of Fortune”. Cambridge, Mass: Polity Press, 2014.). Many problems consequently remained unsolved. To deepen the analysis of the civil-military relations in Brazil, we will give special focus on the last decade only.

Nonetheless, it is worth recalling that the Amnesty Law of 1979 protected military interests from the necessary accountability for their human rights violations during the dictatorship. And they further ensured that they would not be held accountable for their crimes through pressuring and oversighting the formulation of the last Constitution and the final report of Truth Committee of 2012, protecting them to this day (Soares, 2019SOARES, S. A. “Da Constituinte à Comissão Nacional da Verdade: A Questão Militar como Entrave Perene ao Estado de Direito e à Democracia no Brasil”. Perseu, Vol. 13, Nr. 18, pp. 151-165, 2019.). In article 142 of the Constitution, the Law and Order Guarantee Operations (LOGOS) were established. This maintained an institutional role for the Armed Forces in the domestic arena, which expanded over the years, especially through Complementary Laws 97, 117 and 136, and Decree 3.987. The military continue to operate internally on several fronts (Santos, Pinto, Fayal, 2019, p. 226SANTOS, J. C; PINTO, J. C; FAYAL, R. A. F. F. “Armed Forces and Internal Security: Reflections on Civil-Military Relations in Brazil”. Repats, Nr. 2, pp. 206-231, 2019.). Furthermore, the balance of competences in defense issues has continued to favor the Armed Forces (Bruneau et al., 2006BRUNEAU, T. C. et al. “Ministries of defense and democratic control 2005”. In: BRUNEAU, T. C., TOLLEFSON, S. D. (eds.). Who guards the guardians, and how: modern civil-military relations. Austin: University of Texas Press, 2006. pp. 71-101.; Pion-Berlin, 2005PION-BERLIN, D.. “Political management of the military in Latin America”. Military Review, pp. 19-3, 2005.; 2006PION-BERLIN, D.. “The defense wisdom deficit in Latin America: a reply to Thomas C. Bruneau”. Revista Fuerzas Armadas y Sociedad, Vol. 20, Nr. 1, pp. 51-62, 2006.; Pion-Berlin, Trinkunas, 2007PION-BERLIN, D.; TRINKUNAS, H. Attention deficits: why politicians ignore defense policy in Latin America. Latin American Research Review. v. 42, n. 3, 2007. p. 76-100.).

It is important to note that there are many forms of military meddling in civilian governments that are not necessarily a classic coup d’état or violent overthrow of a particular government. Saint-Pierre (2002)SAINT-PIERRE, H. L. “Formas não-golpistas de presença militar no estado”. Perspectivas (24-5), São Paulo, pp. 115-130, 2002. points out that the military in Brazil perceive themselves as sovereign, above usual politics, and sometimes have civilian support in this perception, utilizing several means of political leverage and control. The author elaborates a taxonomy in which he demonstrates that the 1988 Constitution was inadequate regarding the military due to the ambiguity about their precise role. Furthermore, according to Saint-Pierre’s taxonomy, the forces’ participation in politics can be deviant, serving corporate interests or using public office to influence the national debate and pursue substantive changes with or without formal constitutional attributions. Civilian rule can also consent to or concede deviant functions to the military, or the military can impose itself in these roles, which are present in Brazil. This relates to what Huntington called “subjective control”:

military institutions that only reflect social values may be incapable of efficiently fulfilling their specific function” and “Countries that cannot maintain a balanced civil-military relationship are wasting resources and subject to incalculable risks” (Huntington, 1957, p. 20HUNTINGTON, S. P. “The Soldier and the State: The Theory and Politics of Civil-Military Relations”. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Univ. Press, 1957.).

These deviant attributions are neither in accordance with the military ethics developed in the first section nor the democratic parameters presented in the second section. The two decades following the 1988 Constitution were marked by events which seemed to favor civilian supremacy, but other events were clear signs of regression in democratic consolidation. These apparent contradictions were the topic of considerable academic debate. Some authors have highlighted initiatives such as the creation of the Defense Ministry in 1999; the publication of the National Defense Strategy in 2008 and Brazil’s first national defense white paper in 2012; the Truth Committee in 2012; and the participation of civilians, including as ministers of defense, and the concurrent training of defense scholars (D’Araujo, 2010D’ARAUJO, M. C. “Militares, democracia, e desenvolvimento: Brasil e América do Sul”. Rio de Janeiro: FGV Editora, 2010.; Amorim Neto, 2012AMORIM NETO, O. “Democracy, Civil-Military Relations, and Defense Policy in Brazil Brazilian”. Rio de Janeiro: School of Public and Business Administration (EBAPE) Getulio Vargas Foundation, 2012.; Figueiredo, 2010FIGUEIREDO, E. “Os estudos estratégicos, a defesa nacional e a segurança internacional”. In: LESSA, R. (ed.). Horizontes das Ciências Sociais no Brasil: Ciência Política. São Paulo: Barcarolla, 2010.; Hunter, 1997HUNTER, W. “Eroding military influence in Brazil: politicians against soldiers”. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1997.). Others, however, argued that the basis of civilian supremacy was weak, and this “optimistic period” would be transitory, highlighting the prerogatives of the Armed Forces for internal law and order, budgets, intelligence, and national security attributions (Zaverucha, 2005ZAVERUCHA, J. “FHC, forças armadas e polícia: entre o autoritarismo e a democracia”. Rio de Janeiro: Record, 2005.; Bruneau, 2018BRUNEAU, T. C. “Democratic Politics in Brazil: Advances in Accountability Mechanisms and Regression in Civil- Military Relations”. Monterey, California: Naval Postgraduate School, 2018.; Cortinhas, Vitelli, 2020CORTINHAS, J. S., VITELLI, M. G. “Limitações das reformas para o controle civil sobre as forças armadas nos governos do PT (2003-2016)”. Rev. Bras. Est. Def., Vol. 7, Nr. 2, pp. 187-216, 2020.; Winand; Saint-Pierre, 2010WINAND, E., SAINT-PIERRE, H. “A fragilidade da condução política da defesa no Brasil”. História. Vol. 29, Nr. 2, pp. 3-29, 2010.). The latter view was corroborated by subsequent events. The increasing number of domestic missions through LOGOS, the weak role of the legislative, and the occupation of pivotal positions in government are some indicators of the weakness of civilian control in present-day Brazil.

Soares (2019)SOARES, S. A. “Da Constituinte à Comissão Nacional da Verdade: A Questão Militar como Entrave Perene ao Estado de Direito e à Democracia no Brasil”. Perseu, Vol. 13, Nr. 18, pp. 151-165, 2019. argues that the role of the Brazilian military over the last thirty years is characterized by a perspective focused on domestic issues rather than one aiming to protect Brazilian sovereignty and guard against external threats. The author (2019, p. 162) highlights the military’s self-attributed mission to be “protector of the nation” in its own identity. Regarding LOGOS, there were 132 operations between 1992 and 2018, and a brigade was created exclusively for these operations. One highly problematic issue was a change in the military penal code in 2017 which determined that crimes perpetrated by the Armed Forces against civilian lives in these operations would no longer be answerable in the civilian justice system but rather by military proceedings. According to Santos, Pinto and Fayal (2019)SANTOS, J. C; PINTO, J. C; FAYAL, R. A. F. F. “Armed Forces and Internal Security: Reflections on Civil-Military Relations in Brazil”. Repats, Nr. 2, pp. 206-231, 2019., the number of LOGOS substantially increased over time, with around 5 per year from 2000-2017 compared to just under 3 per year from 1989 to 1999. These operations vary in their purpose, from security to basic sanitation, health, national infrastructure, and distribution of vital resources (Santos, Pinto, Fayal, 2019SANTOS, J. C; PINTO, J. C; FAYAL, R. A. F. F. “Armed Forces and Internal Security: Reflections on Civil-Military Relations in Brazil”. Repats, Nr. 2, pp. 206-231, 2019.). The movement out of the barracks towards political engagement should be viewed negatively in terms of the risks created in the system of political power as the military ascends in its political role. This is in clear opposition to the democratic indicators highlighted in section 2 of this paper.

Scholars have argued that civilian supremacy requires significant congressional participation. For instance, Donadio (2004)DONADIO, M. “El papel del parlamento en la defensa nacional”. Revista Fuerzas Armadas y Sociedad, Vol. 18, Nr. 1-2, pp. 139-154, 2004. states that the greater influence the legislative has over defense, the stronger the civilian control over the military. Greater involvement can provide transparency and legitimacy, and a stronger role for society will bring greater stability to defense policy. Crucial in this aspect are parliamentary committees which provide oversight for the military (Pion-Berlin, 2005PION-BERLIN, D.. “Political management of the military in Latin America”. Military Review, pp. 19-3, 2005.; Giraldo, 2006GIRALDO, J. K. “Legislatures and national defense: global comparisons”. In: BRUNEAU, T. C., TOLLEFSON, S. D. (eds.) Who guards the guardians, and how: modern civil-military relations. Austin: University of Texas Press, 2006. pp. 34-71.). Brazilian legislative oversight is weak, with no summoning of ministers, freedom of information requests, public hearings, or active and influential committees. Legislative elites lack the proper knowledge to act as assessors in defense matters (Jungmann, 2009, p. 8JUNGMANN, R. (ed.). “Discursos proferidos na ocasião do lançamento da Frente Parlamentar da Defesa Nacional”. Brasília: Câmara dos Deputados – Coordenação de Publicações, 2009.). All the above contributes to making matters of defense exclusive to military personnel. Another highly problematic issue is budgeting and proposed military projects, which are not closely reviewed by the legislative and have a direct impact on national defense, strengthening the forces’ corporate privileges. According to Castro Santos (2005)CASTRO SANTOS, M. H. “Controles parlamentares e os militares no Brasil: audiências públicas e requerimentos de informação, 1995-2004”. In: LLANOS, M., MUSTAPIC, A. M. (eds.). Controle parlamentar na Alemanha, na Argentina e no Brasil. Rio de Janeiro: Fundação Konrad Adenauer, 2005., military proposals pass the lower and upper house almost by consensus, without proper debate and scrutiny.

There are other problems. The Defense Ministry’s structure, even if led by a civilian, must be evaluated in the context of a broader constitutional arrangement. What civilian instruments guide the formulation of defense policy? Answering this requires further analysis of the Ministry’s composition and not only its formal structure, which according to Cortinhas and Vitelli (2020)CORTINHAS, J. S., VITELLI, M. G. “Limitações das reformas para o controle civil sobre as forças armadas nos governos do PT (2003-2016)”. Rev. Bras. Est. Def., Vol. 7, Nr. 2, pp. 187-216, 2020. favors the military’s pivotal role in decision-making. The Defense Ministry has never really been staffed by civilians (Bruneau, 2018BRUNEAU, T. C. “Democratic Politics in Brazil: Advances in Accountability Mechanisms and Regression in Civil- Military Relations”. Monterey, California: Naval Postgraduate School, 2018.), so the required transparency of defense policy is even more dampened, and the Armed Forces enjoy a near monopoly. Cortinhas and Vitelli (2020)CORTINHAS, J. S., VITELLI, M. G. “Limitações das reformas para o controle civil sobre as forças armadas nos governos do PT (2003-2016)”. Rev. Bras. Est. Def., Vol. 7, Nr. 2, pp. 187-216, 2020. argue that there has been an increase in the institutional autonomy of the Armed Forces, with the pivotal positions in the Ministry—involving for example, resource distribution (important in matters of defense) and civilian control—headed by military officers.

It is clear, then, that there has been a downgrading of civilian control over the last decade, especially following President Dilma Rousseff’s impeachment. President Temer started by recreating the Office for Institutional Security (GSI – Gabinete de Segurança Institucional) and appointed the influential Sérgio Etchehegoyen to lead it, reestablishing the office’s control over intelligence services by presidential decree (8793/2016). In addition, General Walter Braga Neto was appointed as federal intervener for “peacekeeping” in Rio de Janeiro, intensifying the LOGOS’ role. Braga Neto went on to become Bolsonaro’s Chief of Staff and subsequently defense minister. Public statements made by General Villas Bôas concerning former President Lula’s supreme court trial, pressuring the Judges to vote to discount his constitutional rights, add to the long list of troubling examples. By the end of Temer’s term, the Armed Forces held positions in eight important ministries and had been appointed to key secretariats and bureaus.

A recent study by the Instituto de Pesquisa Econômica Aplicada (IPEA) presents important data regarding the increasing role of the military in the federal government. From 2016 to 2020 there was a 102.2% growth in the number of military staff occupying civilian functions in the federal administration, and from 2013 to 2021 the number of military personnel employed in state owned enterprises increased from 6 to 96 (Schmidt, 2022SCHMIDT, F. H. “Presença de militares em cargos e funções comissionadas do Executivo federal”. IPEA, Vol. 1, Nr. 1, 2022.). An interesting fact is that the Army accounted, by 2021, for more than 50% of the origin of this staff, while the Navy and the Air Force were responsible for approximately 20% of the assigned positions each (Schmidt, 2022SCHMIDT, F. H. “Presença de militares em cargos e funções comissionadas do Executivo federal”. IPEA, Vol. 1, Nr. 1, 2022.). Moreover, while the defense budget has averaged 1.5% of the GDP in the past decades (Sipri, 2022SIPRI Military Expenditure Database. “Military expenditure by country as a percentage of gross domestic product, 1949-2020”. Available at: https://www.sipri.org/databases/milex. Accessed on: 13 June 2022.
https://www.sipri.org/databases/milex...
), around 80% of that was destined to personnel, a high cost in comparison with other countries (Silva, Teixeira, 2021SILVA, P. F.; TEIXEIRA, A. W. M. “The relationship between defense policy, the defense Budget and force structure in contemporary Brazil”. BRASILIANA: Journal for Brazilian Studies, Vol. 10, Nr. 2, 2021.). This needs to be addressed with scrutiny since it has a direct impact on possible investment resources (for example, affecting R&D expenditure increase). Consequently, further analysis of the budget composition is also pivotal to the civil-military debate, although it is beyond the scope of this paper.

This level of military occupation of the executive was unprecedented in the democratic era, and since the transition to Bolsonaro’s government, the forces’ role in governance has grown even stronger. The GSI has broadened its remit under the leadership of the controversial General Augusto Heleno, who is well-known for statements denigrating democracy. The vice-president of the republic, General Hamilton Mourão, also plays a leading role in government and presents himself as more moderate than, for example, the civilian far-right former ministers Abraham Weintraub, Ernesto Araújo and Ricardo Salles. The fall of these “ideological” extreme right-wing players can also be seen as representative of a growing role for the military. The Armed Forces gained further control and assumed a “moderator power” role as a tutelary institution of the republic. In the midst of a severe economic crisis, Bolsonaro’s supposedly fiscally conservative government increased military budgets and benefits for personnel while cutting welfare spending on civilians. Furthermore, during the terrible mismanagement of the COVID-19 pandemic, General Eduardo Pazuello was appointed health minister. This resulted in accusations that, for example, the government had promoted ineffective treatments such as chloroquine and ivermectin and was negligent in vaccine procurement as well as allegations of corruption, as the Congressional Investigative Commission (CPI) is now revealing. Even after leaving office, Pazuello, a serving officer, participated in a public demonstration in Rio de Janeiro, violating the army’s own disciplinary code. His violation was investigated by the military and the judgement sealed for 100 years. He now holds the office of Secretary for Strategic Affairs in the Secretariat for Strategic Affairs (Secretaria de Assuntos Estratégicos). It is evident that civilian control over the military is very weak and that there is a long way to go before Brazilian democracy is consolidated.

Indeed, by all the indicators presented in the literature on civil-military relations, Brazil is moving further away from civilian control. The transition to a fully democratic regime was never completed, and the military never lost its prerogatives. This opens institutional space for them to exercise tutelage or act as a “moderator power” in face of a “socialist threat” or “widespread corruption,” among many other never fully verified internal problems. For these reasons, the concluding section of this paper proposes a series of actions that could lead to genuine civilian control. We do this using the lenses of the solid ethical and political values desirable in a democracy and the instruments we proposed above.

Final Remarks

In this paper, we sorted out the main outlines of a military ethics capable of justifying (using the metaethical and normative assumptions of the Triple Theory) the proper moral requirements in civil-military relations within a constitutional democratic regime. Moreover, based on the civil-military relations literature, we reconstructed the parameters and indicators which demonstrate the extent of consolidation in a democratic regime with civilian supremacy, for instance, the precise role attributed to the Armed Forces. Afterwards, we reviewed recent events in Brazil which demonstrate that the transition to full democracy is incomplete given the roles still played by the military in internal affairs.

Based on our findings, we propose the following actions to rectify the problems in civil-military relations and move in the direction of a fully democratic state:

  1. redefine the constitutional role of the Armed Forces, clearly limiting their remit to protecting the country from external threats;

  2. forbid active military personnel from occupying positions in government, as already proposed by PEC 21/2021;

  3. compel the Armed Forces to remain apolitical and neutral in the sense of not participating in public political engagement such as popular demonstrations;

  4. strengthen the role of congress by: i) summoning ministers, allowing freedom of information requests, and holding public hearings; ii) establishing the role of commissions, especially regarding budgets and accountability, so that it can perform a greater role in defense matters;

  5. create civilian positions in the Defense Ministry, especially in auditing (fiscal and compliance), budgetary analysis, appropriations studies, among others;

  6. try military common crimes in civilian courts, revoking the change in Military Code of 2017;

  7. open national defense debates to involve legislative and civilian actors, such as universities and firms, to enhance defense policy, technological innovation, and so on.

Rectifying the civil-military relations in Brazil through these actions and moving in the direction of a fully democratic state is optimific, universally willable and would not be rejected by a reasonable person.

In conclusion, the military is not the patron of the nation: it should not act as a “moderator power” or interfere by positioning itself politically. It must be subordinated to civilian control. The return of the military to the barracks benefits both the country and the military. The Armed Forces could improve their performance in defense matters, by solely focusing on their designated missions and enhancing their professionalism. For the country, it would not only be more efficient in economic terms, but it would also help to strengthen our democracy and political stability.

  • **
    The author would like to thank The National Council for Scientific and Technological Development (CNPq) for financial support of his research project.
  • ***
    The author would like to thank Eugenio Diniz, David Mares and Samuel Soares for their contributions.

References

  • ACADEMIA MILITAR DAS AGULHAS NEGRAS. (http://www.aman.eb.mil.br/)
    » http://www.aman.eb.mil.br/
  • ALBRIGHT, D. E. “A Comparative Conceptualization of Civil-Military Relations”. World Politics Nr. 32, pp. 553-576, 1980.
  • ALLISON, G. T. “Essence of Decision: Explaining the Cuban Missile Crisis”. Boston: Little, Brown, 1969.
  • ALLISON, G. T., HALPERIN, M. H. “Bureaucratic Politics: A Paradigm and Some Policy Implications”. World Politics Nr. 24, p. 40–79, 1972.
  • AMORIM NETO, O. “Democracy, Civil-Military Relations, and Defense Policy in Brazil Brazilian”. Rio de Janeiro: School of Public and Business Administration (EBAPE) Getulio Vargas Foundation, 2012.
  • ARISTOTLE. “Politics”. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995.
  • BAUMANN, D. “Military Ethics: a Task for Armies”. Military Medicine Vol. 172, Nr. suppl_2, November 2007, pp. 34-38. https://doi.org/10.7205/MILMED.173.Supplement_2.34 (Accessed on: 16/09/21).
    » https://doi.org/10.7205/MILMED.173.Supplement_2.34
  • BELKIN, A., SCHOFER E. “Toward a structural understanding of coup risk”. J. Confl. Resolut., 47(5), pp. 594-620, 2003.
  • BINGHAM, T. “The Rule of Law”. London: Penguin, 2011.
  • BÖHMELT, T., PILSTER, U. “The impact of institutional coup-proofing on coup attempts and coup outcomes”. Int. Interact, 41, pp. 158-82, 2015.
  • BORGES, M. L., DALL’AGNOL, D., DUTRA, D.V. «Ética». Rio de Janeiro: DP&A, 2002.
  • BROOKS, R. A. “Integrating the Civil-Military Relations Subfield”. Annu. Rev. Political Sci Vol. 1, pp. 379-398, 2019.
  • BRUNEAU, T. C. “Democratic Politics in Brazil: Advances in Accountability Mechanisms and Regression in Civil- Military Relations”. Monterey, California: Naval Postgraduate School, 2018.
  • BRUNEAU, T. C. et al. “Ministries of defense and democratic control 2005”. In: BRUNEAU, T. C., TOLLEFSON, S. D. (eds.). Who guards the guardians, and how: modern civil-military relations Austin: University of Texas Press, 2006. pp. 71-101.
  • BRUNEAU, T. C., MATEI, F. C., (eds.). “The Routledge Handbook of Civil-Military Relations”. New York: Routledge, 2013.
  • BRUNEAU, T. D., TOLLEFSON, S. D. (eds.). “Who Guards the Guardians and How: Democratic Civil--Military Relations”. Austin, TX: Univ. Texas Press, 2006.
  • CASTRO SANTOS, M. H. “Controles parlamentares e os militares no Brasil: audiências públicas e requerimentos de informação, 1995-2004”. In: LLANOS, M., MUSTAPIC, A. M. (eds.). Controle parlamentar na Alemanha, na Argentina e no Brasil Rio de Janeiro: Fundação Konrad Adenauer, 2005.
  • CASTRO, C. “General Villas Bôas: Conversa com o Comandante”. Rio de Janeiro: FGV Editora, 2021.
  • CORTINHAS, J. S., VITELLI, M. G. “Limitações das reformas para o controle civil sobre as forças armadas nos governos do PT (2003-2016)”. Rev. Bras. Est. Def., Vol. 7, Nr. 2, pp. 187-216, 2020.
  • COSTA, T. G. “Democratization and International Integration: The Role of Armed Forces in Brazil’s Grand Strategy”. In: MARES, D. R. (ed.). Civil-Military Relations New York/London: Routledge, 1998. pp. 223-237.
  • CROISSANT, A., KUEHN (eds.). “Reforming Civil-Military Relations in New Democracies: Democratic Control and Military Effectiveness in Comparative Perspectives”. Chame: Springer, 2017.
  • D’ARAUJO, M. C. “Militares, democracia, e desenvolvimento: Brasil e América do Sul”. Rio de Janeiro: FGV Editora, 2010.
  • DAHL, R. “On Democracy”. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1998.
  • DE BRUIN, E. “Preventing coups d’état: how counterbalancing works”. J. Confl. Resolut, 62(7), pp. 1-26, 2018.
  • DINIZ, E., ROCHA, A. “Ir além da PEC Pazuello”. Valor Econômico 23 August 2021. https://valor.globo.com/opiniao/coluna/ir-alem-da-pec-pazuello.ghtml (Accessed on: 13/10/21).
    » https://valor.globo.com/opiniao/coluna/ir-alem-da-pec-pazuello.ghtml
  • DONADIO, M. “El papel del parlamento en la defensa nacional”. Revista Fuerzas Armadas y Sociedad, Vol. 18, Nr. 1-2, pp. 139-154, 2004.
  • DWORKIN, R. “Levando os Direitos a Sério”. São Paulo: Martins Fontes, 2005.
  • FEAVER, P. “Civil-Military Relations and Policy: A Sampling of a New Wave of Scholarship”. Journal of Strategic Studies, 40 (1-2), pp. 325-342, 2017.
  • FEAVER, P.. “Civil-Military Relations”. Annual Review of Political Science, Vol. 2, pp. 211-241, June 1999.
  • FIGUEIREDO, E. “Os estudos estratégicos, a defesa nacional e a segurança internacional”. In: LESSA, R. (ed.). Horizontes das Ciências Sociais no Brasil: Ciência Política São Paulo: Barcarolla, 2010.
  • FORDHAM, B. O. “Military Interests and Civilian Politics: The Influence of the Civil Military ‘Gap’ on Peacetime Military Policy”. In: FEAVER, P., KOHN, R. (eds.). Soldiers and Civilians: The Civil-Military Gap and American National Security. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2001. pp. 355-85.
  • GASSEBNER, M., GUTMAN, J., VOIGT, S. “When to expect a coup d’état? An extreme bounds analysis of coup determinants”. Public Choice, 169(3), pp. 293-31, 2016.
  • GIRALDO, J. K. “Legislatures and national defense: global comparisons”. In: BRUNEAU, T. C., TOLLEFSON, S. D. (eds.) Who guards the guardians, and how: modern civil-military relations Austin: University of Texas Press, 2006. pp. 34-71.
  • GRAHAM, K. “The Battle of Democracy. Conflict, Consensus and the Individual”. Brighton: Wheatsheaf Books, 1986.
  • GUTMANN, A. “Democracy”. In: GOODIN, R. E., PETTIT, P. A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy Oxford: Blackwell, 1995. pp. 411-421
  • HUNTER, W. “Eroding military influence in Brazil: politicians against soldiers”. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1997.
  • HUNTINGTON, S. P. “The Soldier and the State: The Theory and Politics of Civil-Military Relations”. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Univ. Press, 1957.
  • JUNGMANN, R. (ed.). “Discursos proferidos na ocasião do lançamento da Frente Parlamentar da Defesa Nacional”. Brasília: Câmara dos Deputados – Coordenação de Publicações, 2009.
  • KANT, I. “Practical Philosophy”. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008.
  • LEE, S. “Ethics and Democracy. An Introduction”. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012.
  • LEVITSKY, S., ZIBLATT, D. “How Democracies Die”. New York: Crown Publishing, 2018.
  • LOCKE, J. “Two Treatises of Government”. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994.
  • MARES, D. R. (ed.). “Civil-Military Relations. Building Democracy and Regional Security in Latin America, Southern Asia, and Central Europe”. New York/London: Routledge, 1998.
  • MARES, D. R., MARTÍNEZ, R. (eds.). “Debating Civil-Military Relations in Latin America”. Brighton: Sussex Academic Press, 2014.
  • MARTÍNEZ, R. “Objectives for Democratic Consolidation in the Armed Forces”. In: MARES, D. R., MARTÍNEZ, R. Debating Civil-Military Relations in Latin America Brighton: Sussex Academic Press, 2014. pp. 21-60.
  • MONTERO, A. P. “Brazil: Reversal of Fortune”. Cambridge, Mass: Polity Press, 2014.
  • NIELSEN S. C., SNIDER D. M. (eds.). “American Civil-Military Relations: The Soldier and the State in a New Era”. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins Univ. Press, 2009.
  • NORDLINGER, E. A. “Soldiers in Politics: Military Coups and Governments”. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1977.
  • PARFIT, D. “On What Matters”. (2v.) Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013.
  • PERLMUTTER, A. “The Praetorian State and the Praetorian Army: Towards a Taxonomy of Civil Military Relations in Developing Polities”. Comparative Politics, Vol. 1, Nr. 3, pp. 382-404, 1969.
  • PION-BERLIN, D. “Through Corridors of Power: Institutions and Civil–Military Relations in Argentina”. University Park, PA: Pa. State Univ. Press, 1997.
  • PION-BERLIN, D.. “Political management of the military in Latin America”. Military Review, pp. 19-3, 2005.
  • PION-BERLIN, D.. “The defense wisdom deficit in Latin America: a reply to Thomas C. Bruneau”. Revista Fuerzas Armadas y Sociedad, Vol. 20, Nr. 1, pp. 51-62, 2006.
  • PION-BERLIN, D.; TRINKUNAS, H. Attention deficits: why politicians ignore defense policy in Latin America. Latin American Research Review. v. 42, n. 3, 2007. p. 76-100.
  • POWELL, J. M. “Determinants of the attempting and outcome of coups d’état”. J. Confl. Resolut. 56(6), pp. 1017-1040, 2012.
  • RAWLS, J. “A Theory of Justice”. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999.
  • SAINT-PIERRE, H. L. “Formas não-golpistas de presença militar no estado”. Perspectivas (24-5), São Paulo, pp. 115-130, 2002.
  • SANTOS, J. C; PINTO, J. C; FAYAL, R. A. F. F. “Armed Forces and Internal Security: Reflections on Civil-Military Relations in Brazil”. Repats, Nr. 2, pp. 206-231, 2019.
  • SCHMIDT, F. H. “Presença de militares em cargos e funções comissionadas do Executivo federal”. IPEA, Vol. 1, Nr. 1, 2022.
  • SILVA, P. F.; TEIXEIRA, A. W. M. “The relationship between defense policy, the defense Budget and force structure in contemporary Brazil”. BRASILIANA: Journal for Brazilian Studies, Vol. 10, Nr. 2, 2021.
  • SINGER, P. (ed.). “Does Anything Really Matter? Essays on Parfit on Objectivity”. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017.
  • SIPRI Military Expenditure Database. “Military expenditure by country as a percentage of gross domestic product, 1949-2020”. Available at: https://www.sipri.org/databases/milex Accessed on: 13 June 2022.
    » https://www.sipri.org/databases/milex
  • SOARES, S. A. “Da Constituinte à Comissão Nacional da Verdade: A Questão Militar como Entrave Perene ao Estado de Direito e à Democracia no Brasil”. Perseu, Vol. 13, Nr. 18, pp. 151-165, 2019.
  • STEPAN. “The new professionalism of internal warfare and military role expansion”. In: STEPAN, A. (ed.) Authoritarian Brazil: Origins, Politics and Future New Haven, CT: Yale Univ. Press, 1973. pp. 47-69.
  • TEN, C. L. “Constitutionalism and the rule of law”. In: GOODIN, R. E., PETTIT, P. A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy Oxford: Blackwell, 1995. pp. 394-403.
  • THOMPSON, W. R. “Grievances of Military Coup-Makers”. Beverly Hills, CA: Sage, 1973.
  • WALZER, M. “Just and Unjust Wars. A Moral Argument with Historical Illustrations”. New York: Basic Books, 2000.
  • WINAND, E., SAINT-PIERRE, H. “A fragilidade da condução política da defesa no Brasil”. História. Vol. 29, Nr. 2, pp. 3-29, 2010.
  • ZAVERUCHA, J. “FHC, forças armadas e polícia: entre o autoritarismo e a democracia”. Rio de Janeiro: Record, 2005.

Publication Dates

  • Publication in this collection
    29 May 2023
  • Date of issue
    Apr 2023

History

  • Received
    02 Nov 2021
  • Accepted
    14 Sept 2022
Faculdade de Filosofia e Ciências Humanas da UFMG Av. Antônio Carlos, 6627 Campus Pampulha, CEP: 31270-301 Belo Horizonte MG - Brasil, Tel: (31) 3409-5025, Fax: (31) 3409-5041 - Belo Horizonte - MG - Brazil
E-mail: kriterion@fafich.ufmg.br