1. INTRODUCTION
The customary image of the French thinker René Descartes disseminated in some systematic philosophy is that of a rationalist with unconvincing theological commitments involved with unequal success in modern mathematics and physics. Currently, this image of the so-called father of modern philosophy also has a clear negative connotation, Descartes' legend presents him as the main defender of a pernicious "official doctrine"1 characterized by infallible introspection, epistemic and ontic mental privacy (first person authority), transparency of mind, and especially a radical dualism as the basis of all these problematic features.2
We might offer a hopeful perspective to this description or perhaps negative diagnosis: the conceptual analysis of twentieth-century philosophy of language and mind, as well as the experimental advances in cognitive sciences and neuropsychology, would have rebutted the Cartesian myth. Thus, even if we believe Descartes' invention of mind,3 it would not be necessary to accept his alleged thesis of the autonomy of consciousness in relation to bodily and worldly acts.
To the extent that physicalism has become a "true" and all-encompassing theory, few feel inclined to subscribe to the dogma of the Ghost in the Machine4 or the profoundly anti-scientific view of material and immaterial interactions.5 In fact, "Descartes' error" would involve his understanding of the body and mind as something radically different - and even opposite - rendering their interaction unintelligible.6
Certainly, Descartes was part of what we now call “new science” in contrast to influential Aristotelian scholasticism, but the lexicon and point of view of his Meditations on First Philosophy or his Principles of Philosophy remained indebted to the dominant doctrine; unanimously, the critics of his time (Hobbes, Arnauld or Gassendi, among others) understood that the scholastic notion of "substance" was central for understanding Cartesian dualism. According to this ideal interpretation, substance would be something similar to the unconscious basis of Cartesian ontology and "anthropology."7
Thus, thought and extension would be the attributes of two distinct and irreconcilable substances (the only ones existing along with the divine): res cogitans or the mind, which is pure, indivisible, and always identical to itself and enjoys essential individuality; and the bodies in which the res extensa expresses itself, which are composed and indefinitely divisible with temporary individuality. In this sense, to conceive the subject or thinking substance and to achieve the full consciousness of the immaterial being, as Taylor noted,8 we should observe the ontological fissure: the mind must objectify our ordinary embodied perspective, disconnecting us from the world (including here another ego). The ego cogito thus emerges from hyperbolic doubt thanks to an undoubted self-knowledge that abhors the body and all other things that particularize and question it, such as biography, memory or context.9
Can we really imagine our own disembodied existence or an existence with a body different from the one we have? As some thinkers have objected,10 such a thing may not be possible from a linguistic viewpoint, and, furthermore, such a mind would lack all our proprioceptive and exteroceptive experiences, as well as the beliefs and intentions attached to them. In addition, this hypothesis leaves many elements to be explained, such as the problem of the interaction between corporeal and mental substances, particularly its difficult link with the notion of causality, efficient, or occasional.11 Last, this position does not fit well with some current scientific advances. Relevant empirical studies, such as Damasio's somatic marker hypothesis,12 show that the more refined operations of the mind do not seem to be separated from the structure and functioning of the biological organism. In particular, so-called guttural emotions which have a clearer corporeal origin, play a relevant role in practical reasoning and in our decision making.
Thus, we continue understanding the mind in terms of the supposedly Cartesian notion as a self-contained entity, transparent to itself and only accidentally connected with external elements (including our body). However, the philosophical leanings that have woven the legend of Descartes has proven to be influential and predicts a short future for the illusion of the Cartesian consciousness.
However, we could ask whether this smear campaign corresponds to what we find in a full and complete, non-fragmentary and contextualized reading of Descartes' work. Is Cartesian thought, at this point, an idea of a subject as substance and an idea of consciousness as only accidentally related to a body with which it establishes a mysterious causal interaction? Is Cartesian consciousness a dispassionate ghost inserted into a cold machine? The answer to these questions in this article is going to be a resounding no, but to substantiate our answer, we will not directly object to the hypothesis of some of the main proponents of the legend (such as Ryle or Damasio).13
Instead, we suggest contextualizing Descartes' thought, placing it in his time and considering that it is closely related to the medical tradition and the advances of “new science”. We also want to heed the Cartesian recommendation of reading him in a comprehensive way,14 considering works such as The Treatise on Man or The Passions of the Soul - which are usually disdained or misinterpreted - as well as part of his correspondence. Finally, we will propose a new look a Cartesian thought that, without denying dualism, heeds the unity of the vrai homme, the passionate character of the embodied mind, and its possible relation to current discussions in philosophy of the mind and cognitive sciences such as the hard problem of consciousness.15
2. THE CARTESIAN BACKGROUND
In every legend, there are real elements, and without a doubt Descartes advocated a real distinction between the immaterial mind and the material body (explicitly, for example, in AT VII: 79/CSM II: 55 but also in many other passages). However, this was not new in his time. In fact, to be fully understood, Cartesian philosophy has to be placed in the context of discussions about Christian anthropology in medieval and Renaissance scholastic thinking.16
In this debate, in which both Plato's work and the studies of Aristotle on the soul and animals were of great importance, two problems were central: the substantial unity of the person and the principle of individuation.17 The most important issue was to resolve what it is to be a man and the source of their unity, establishing their numerical and qualitative identity according to an essential dilemma: matter or form. The terms of this alternative were mainly those of the substantial form of Aristotelian scholastic hylomorphism18 and the option of Duns Scotus centered in the mind.19
It is clear that Descartes, in accordance with his critique of Aristotelianism, chose to understand the mind as a source of uniqueness, and there is a transcript of his well-known distinction between the mental and the corporeal areas. However, the cogito in its intimate structure includes modes of consciousness linked to the corporeal, such as the imagination or the senses, which from the beginning hindered the possibility of a complete self-transparency of a lonely mind:
But what then am I? A thing that thinks. What is that? A thing that doubts, understands, affirms, denies, is willing, is unwilling, and also imagines and has sensory perceptions (AT VII: 20/CSM II: 19).
Bodily opacity would thus hinder Cartesian attempts of self-knowledge, in keeping with the importance of soul-searching in the wake of the religious movements of the Reformation and Counter-Reformation. Thus, by incorporating these modes into mental phenomenology, by attempting to embrace all modalities of human experience, he left the door open to a type of subconscious avant la lettre.20
However, beyond these limitations, Cartesian dualism is linked to a polemical position towards the dominant doctrine not only in scholasticism but also in the physiology of its time. His contemporaries thought that the soul, mainly following Aristotle, was the principle of nourishment, growth, and movement of every living being (adding intellect and will in human beings), but for Descartes, the spirit, assimilated to the consciousness, could not be the substantial form of the body, the agency that directs all its operations.
However, to correctly understand the critical and innovative nature of the Cartesian proposal, it must be placed within the framework of a much greater transformation, which was carried out in the conception of Nature inherited from the Aristotelian magisterium. For Aristotle, the key distinction in defining the phýsis is to be established between external and internal causes of movement, with Nature being the principle of internal movement.21 In addition, a theoretical distinction could be made between matter and form as constituents of Nature: the natural form would be internal to the moved thing, and the tripartite soul would become the substantial form of each living being.22
However, with the advances of the “new science” and taking into account the essential contributions of Galileo or Descartes himself, among others, Nature ceased to be conceived as the internal principle of movement and began to be understood as the arena of time-space transformations of matter under universal mathematical laws. Consistent with this, the basic elements of Cartesian physics included the identification of matter with the extension and the postulation of three laws: (1) the persistence of states of matter; (2) the rectilinear tendency of the corpuscles and 3) the local conservation of the amount of movement in collisions between particles of matter (AT VII: 62-65/CSM I: 240-242). These three rules would govern the movements and interactions of every part of matter in the plenum (for, as is well known, Descartes rejected the existence of the void) without any reference to substantial forms or final causes.
Thus, in contrast to the traditional Aristotelian scholastic conception in which matter and form are principles of a substance that are only separated verbally, Descartes would understand that hylomorphism constitutes an illusion: a mere abstraction when conceived separately, the form would not contribute to explaining how the matter informed becomes a subject of action and an object of passion.23
Thus, forms were no longer conceived as causes and principles of Nature. The soul would cease to be the general biological principle of vital warmth and movement, and these functions would be brought back to the mechanism of the body, whose parts would be subject to the same laws as the rest of the physical world. In addition, the spirit would come to be understood as consciousness or mind, also rejecting the traditional hierarchical division of parts of the soul - a higher one devoted to reasoning and others that are lower and centered in the emotional and appetitive side.24 Finally, thought would no longer be understood as a holistic principle and is instead now placed inside the brain at the pineal gland, with whose bodily movements it would establish relations of mutual affection or association (AT XI: 129/CSM I: 100; AT XI: 351-353/CSM I: 340).
Thus, Descartes is credited as virtually the first to initiate a micro-mechanical approach to physiology.25 In line with what has just been discussed, his purpose would have been to transform all the functions in the body traditionally assigned to the sensory and vegetative soul, reducing consciousness and its modes to its mental dimension.
Although the medicine of his time, predominantly Galenic (and ultimately Aristotelian), greatly influenced Descartes,26 it cannot be said that his anatomical and experimental studies gave rise to suitable descriptions in general terms;27 doubtlessly, his iatromechanical perspective allowed him to transform the inherited conception of the body. Accordingly, where previous physiologists had invoked incorporeal powers, faculties, or agents, to offer explanations of living things, Descartes only appealed to matter in motion, organized as a machine whose pieces fitted perfectly (in contrast with the holism of the Aristotelian form) and function automatically:28
I should like you to consider that these functions follow from the mere arrangement of the machine's organs every bit as naturally as the movements of a clock or other automaton follow from the arrangement of its counter-weights and wheels. To explain these functions, then, it is no necessary to conceive of this machine as having any vegetative or sensitive soul or other principle of movement and life (…)(AT XI: 202/CSM I: 108).
In addition, by modifying the conception of the body, Descartes also altered its relationship with mental states. Here, although Descartes’ ideas may be considered in many senses a precedent for neuro-anatomical studies such as those carried out by Damasio,29 he was not a reductivist because he considered the existence of mental experiences, the reality of a consciousness that accompanies and interprets the body movements of the mechanism to which it is inextricably linked, undeniable. However, to account for this point, we must go to the next section and consider the emotions of the embodied mind.
3. THE TRUE MAN AS A SUBSTRATUM OF PASSION
Regarding passion in the work of Descartes, two elements are usually held that are different and, at least initially, contradictory. On the one hand, we are told that the French thinker was scarcely original30 and that his supposed invitation to dominate the passions of the soul by reason had a clear rootedness in a tradition beginning with Plato and passing through Aristotle, ending in the Stoic moral. On the other hand, we are told that Descartes would have substituted the moralistic rhetoric of his predecessors with a mechanistic doctrine, leaving aside the teachings of Aristotle and post-Aristotelian thinkers and presenting a sort of reductionist cognitivism in his conception of emotions. 31 In short, this contradiction would reveal the last-minute character of Descartes' physiological and moral reflections.
However, the former can be fair. Although Descartes' later works propose a therapy for passion and insist on moderation and indirect control, as we shall see below, their aim can hardly be linked to the Stoic ideal of elimination of passion, since Descartes considers passion an error of judgment. Although it is true that Descartes himself claims that he wants to explain passion "only as a natural philosopher, and not as a rhetorician or even as a moral philosopher" (AT XI: 326/CSM I: 327), this restriction literally reiterates a thesis of Aristotle: "This at once makes it the business of the natural philosopher to inquire into the soul (…)".32 It is also clear to any reader of The Passions that Descartes does not limit himself to describing these ideas in the same terms as a physiologist but instead links it to a phenomenological and moral study.33
Thus, although the French author is not fully original in his approach and cannot even be considered a pioneer in regard to combining and synthesizing two previous approaches to the passions, the medical and moral (as Galen, Avicenna or Thomas of Aquinas, among others, had done before), his proposal is significantly different and much more elaborate than what is normally assumed by those who hold the Cartesian legend. However, to make it clear, we must pay more attention to the passion context in which the Cartesian project unfolded.
In that sense, we can begin by pointing out that the two main moral traditions prevailing in the seventeenth century were the Aristotelian and Stoic traditions.34 The prestige and influence of Aristotle was undoubtedly still significant at this time, but his evaluation of passion, which is basically positive, contrasted with the Christian atmosphere, which linked passion to original sin and the fall of man. Christian doctrine claims that emotions must be controlled strictly by reason and will; therefore, the intellectualist conception of Stoicism, with its ideal of rational mastery, was gaining greater prominence.
Stoics believed that emotions were linked to evaluative judgments that, by their tendency to exaggerate the importance of the self, were false and vicious. It was thus desirable and possible to achieve a state of complete liberation and elimination of bodily passions (apatheia) or at least of its evaluative dimension (since the Stoics admitted the existence of certain preliminary passions (propatheiai) or involuntary movements linked to them are uncontrollable even to the wise).35
Descartes recognized the importance of reason in distinguishing what falls under our control and what does not, but in terms of regulating desires in accordance to reason (AT IV: 264/CSMK: 257; AT XI: 436-440/CSM I: 379-381), he could not agree with Stoic intellectualism or its ideal of the dispassionate wise: "(...) I am not one of those cruel philosophers who pretend that the wise man must be insensitive" (AT IV: 201-202). By assimilating passion to the Stoic preliminary passion to a certain extent and by considering (as the first part of The Passions of the Soul shows) the body's mechanical dimension, the French thinker rejected the possibility of direct control of these areas.
Passion certainly had a mental component for Descartes, and he believed it was possible to influence passion - hence the therapeutic character of the Cartesian proposal and its moral dimension. However, to moderate passion one has to account for the involuntary bodily element, the automatic reaction of the machine to the stimuli of the external world, or the influence of certain patterns of corporeal memory that are fixed in the brain by the animal spirit, which fights against our conscious will and, in many cases, dominates it.
In any case, let us insist that it is possible, and this is what the Cartesian proposal is about: indirect control of the passions that bind us (and which unleash somatic-psychic conflicts, sometimes of great severity and terrible consequences) through the development of attention and certain habits.36 These can give rise to other passions, attenuating those that are harmful to us and contributing, in short, to strengthening those that benefit us (although he indicates to Chanut in a letter dated November 1, 1646, “I have found almost all of them to be good" (AT IV: 538/CSMK: 300), its misuse can become harmful (AT XI: 485-488/CSM I: 370-371)).37
In the same sense, it can be said that the passions also reintroduce the teleological dimension, denied in the Cartesian mechanistic physical system. Although, according to the Aristotelian theoretical framework, life's preservation, for which the divinity instituted the passions first (AT VII: 83/CSM II: 57), is at the lowest level, this is undoubtedly an end and explains the general goodness of emotions. Thus, against Stoic recommendations, passion is seen by Descartes from a genetic perspective as a bodily-mental resource that from early childhood guarantees our health and the care of our bodies and is able to go even further until we are brought to a full inversion of that basic teleology, when love or generosity demand an extreme sacrifice (AT IV: 293-294/CSMK: 266).38
What are passions for Descartes specifically? It is difficult to explain clear and distinctly, considering their dual dimension of mental and corporeal,39 but it can be said that they are ideas or perceptions (in the Cartesian sense of "idea" according to the definition given in his answers to the Second Objections to Meditations on First Philosophy (AT VII: 160-161/CSM II: 113): not images of the imagination but modifications or contents of the pure mind), caused in the mind by the body, in the body as a result of the movements of the animal spirit, or generated by the same mind, modifying the body dispositions (since the relation is biconditional or non-compulsive between the organism and consciousness). In that sense, they adhere to the spirit and are "felt" in the mind but clearly come from "elsewhere", from what is not consciousness, although they can move it as no other thought does (and in that sense, we also call them emotions (AT XI: 349-350/CSM II: 338-339)).40 To sum up, while from a physiological point of view a passion is a corporeal impulse of the animal body (AT V: 278/CSMK: 366), from a psychophysical perspective, “passions of the soul” are modes of the soul that “depend absolutely” on actions of the body (AT XI: 359/CSM I: 343). So, in that last sense, the passively caused passions move the mind.41
The key question, then, is what concrete roles the body and mind play in the passionate dimension of the human being. If the body is the general cause of passions, it would seem that the mind must be a mere spectator, although we have already questioned their merely representational or cognitive characterization. If the mind is active, its purity would be questioned, and one could consider both the rationality of the mental sphere and the reality of the body-mind distinction, eminently postulated in the metaphysical writings of the French thinker.
This is a complex question, which, in essence, considers the reality of the union in the human being and its coherence with the Cartesian real distinction. However, as some authors have noted,42 Descartes tried to consider the passivity of the sensations (internal and external) and the passions as a full mode of the res cogitans mainly during the last period of his life. That is to say, although we indicated that the experiential modalities related to the body already appeared in the Meditations on First Philosophy (with the ego as a thing that thinks, wants, imagines and feels), it is in his late correspondence and his last work where Descartes thinks in more detail about the imagination and the emotions as modalities of the mind that necessarily need the body to be developed.
Thus, in contrast to Aristotle, where action and passion were two mutually combinable categories43 because they referred to one being whose formal and material principles were merely verbal, in the case of Descartes, this combination, while also possible, would take place between different but mutually responsive elements (AT XI: 327-328/CSM I: 327; AT III: 428/CSMK: 193). In the case of passion, then, we speak of a mode of consciousness by means of which the res cogitans would be considered passively without exercising the cause of his own thought in a "general" way or being merely a spectator of their emotions.44
The mode of pure intellection, the intellect as the function of our mind, does not suffer or become impassioned in any way, and inert bodies, pure extension, would not have that discernible facet. We are one with our body because we suffer and we are passionate, according to Descartes, thanks to the passivity mode through corporality. Our flesh feels everything while feeling itself at the same time, and our mind does not experience sensations without the bodily medium acting on our passively understood consciousness.
Keeping this in mind and taking a well-known letter to Mesland of February 9, 1645 (AT IV: 172-175/CSMK: 241-244) as a starting point, where the thinker distinguishes bodies in general from the body of a human being, some authors have proposed an idea of individual as corporeal subjectivity in Descartes.45 Certainly one might point to a sort of ambiguity in his treatment of bodies since, at least in Meditation VI, external bodies are doubtful and their principle of unity is only contingent, in the case of our flesh, on the notion that my body is myself, and its undoubted unity is determined by the consciousness closely linked to it. If I were not united to my body, I would not fully develop all the modes of the human mind, including that of the imagination, which allows me to think about other bodies, which are not mine and are not myself:
First of all, then, I perceived by my senses that I had a head, hands, feet and other limbs making up the body, which I regarded as part of myself, or perhaps even as my whole self. I also perceived by my senses that this body was situated among many other bodies (…) (AT VII: 74/CSM II: 51-52).
In fact, in contrast to the ontological criterion that allowed, on the real distinction level, to separate bodies, which are indefinitely divisible, from the mind without parts in the case of the true man, the substrate of all passions,46 the spirit remains essentially indivisible, but our body and our flesh are also functionally indivisible (as Descartes notes, by virtue of the disposition of the organs, whereby "the removal of any of them renders the whole body defective" (AT XI: 351/CSM I: 339)).47 The passionate body acts as a whole that affects the mind, and it unfolds itself in its own modes through the body and as a body that is passively affected. Both can be conceived but not experienced separately.48
4. THE EMBODIED MIND AND THE HUMAN WORLD
Gassendi was the first to make an objection that would foreshadow many others, such as Damasio’s:
And if you are something separate, how are you compounded with matter so as to make up a unity? Moreover, since all compounding, conjunction or union takes place between the component parts, must there not be some relationship between these parts? Yet what relationship can possibly be understood to exist between corporeal and incorporeal parts? (AT VII: 344/CSM II: 238).
The Cartesian answer, which at the time was not convincing or, rather, did not seem to be an answer at all, consisted of the mere reiteration of something to which we must attend in this last section of the text because it will allow us to understand the specific status of being a passionate human, as Descartes seemed to conceive it, in the context of his time and his writings.
For the French thinker, the bond or interlacing between my body and my mind does not belong to the order of relations that are established between two extended bodies whose corpuscles collide and causally bind (in this sense, the categorical error which Ryle attributes to Descartes would simply be an interpretative error of the Anglo-Saxon author). This certainly agrees with the Cartesian concept of mechanical causality: causal relationships are a function of the extension of bodies and the mind is a thinking and unextended thing.49
In this direction, the multiple analogies that Descartes sets out to show are presented with difficulty, probably due to the lack of an appropriate lexicon, whose description is adequate to give an account of the authentic human being. Additionally, this or the supposed Cartesian explanation, does nothing to establish an accidental connection between diverse substances, as is usually perceived.
Thus, the analogy of the pilot in his vessel negatively expresses how the mind is closely linked to the body and is mixed (permixtio) with it:
(…) I am not merely present in my body as a sailor is present in a ship, but that I am closely joined and, as it were, intermingled with it, so that I and the body form a unit. If this were not so, I, who am nothing but a thinking thing, would not feel pain when the body was hurt but would perceive the damage purely by the intellect, just as a sailor perceives by sight if anything in his ship is broken. Similarly, when the body needed food or drink, I should have an explicit understanding of the fact instead of having confused sensations of hunger and thirst (AT VII: 81/CSM II: 56).50
The meaning of the metaphor is clear: although a pilot has greater knowledge and control of his ship than a common sailor or a simple passenger, the experience of their union is not so intimate as to feel pain when a part breaks down. In this sense, while the link between the pilot and the ship is accidental, the same is not true of the mind-body relationship, which is originally established in an essential and inseparable way.
Other analogies appear to be along the same lines, such as the gravity analogy, which we find in a correspondence with Elisabeth, Princess of Bohemia (in the epistle of May 21, 1643), as well as in the Sixth Replies to her Meditations in a letter to Regius of January 1642, in a letter to father Dinet, and in a letter to Arnauld of July 29, 1648,51 which question the application of causal relationships in the field of the union, proposing in its place a sort of "action at a distance". There is also the analogy of the plumber (AT XI: 131-132/CSM I: 100-101) or that of the arm and the rest of the body (AT VII: 228/CSM II: 160) or the metaphor of the relationship between bones and flesh (AT VII: 423/CSM II: 286).
In short, and although each analogy illuminates a different aspect of the description that Descartes considers correct, it is possible to note as the main result of these metaphors that the mind does not use the body as an object that is alien to it, unlike what it happens in the case of a pilot with his ship or in an angel: "Additionally, I thought I was careful to guard against anyone inferring from this that man was simply 'a soul which makes use of a body'" (AT VII: 227/CSM II: 160). What comes first is the consciousness of unity.52
The restlessness that arises here that is at the basis of the aforementioned Gassendi's objection that would be repeated by many thinkers, such as Kant,53 is how to establish a real distinction between two substances, with the attributes of thought and extension, at the same time as the true union that constitutes the real human being (particularly when we do not find that substantial self, as the aforementioned Kant or Hume noted, in our thinking). However, as some scholars have noted54 there is no need to conceive the ego cogito as a substance: after all, its permanence is only that of an act of thinking, lacking the duration in time and the immutability that is supposed in a substance, except by the ordinary contribution of God.55
Indeed, although substance has a relevant role in Meditations regarding the existence of God and in relation to extended bodies, as far as to mind is concerned, only divine intervention allows us to speak of a substantial finite entity. Thus, if we carefully consider the Aristotelian-scholastic notion of substance as an entity that exists by itself, it must be admitted that it would hardly be applied in the Cartesian case to the ego or consciousness.
This is where the third primitive notion that Descartes expounded to Princess Elisabeth in their correspondence (AT III: 690ff/CSMK: 226ff) would come into play. As it is well known, these notions - the mind, body and the union of both - constitute a new way of referring to the simple natures of the Rules for the Direction of the Mind (AT X: 381ff, 392ff, 410ff/CSM I: 21ff, 28ff, 39ff) and the simple notions that make up our thoughts in the Principles of Philosophy (AT VIII: 22-24/CSM I: 208-209).56 However, in short, the most important idea is that they form the simplest and easiest elements to know from our epistemic perspective and, therefore, they are the patterns from which we elaborate the rest of our knowledge.
Thus, instead of thinking in terms of an extrinsic, causal relationship between irreconcilable substances (ontologically speaking), it is possible to approach this linkage from an epistemic perspective, which considers the primitive character of the union that is conceived from the starting point of our intellectual capacities and is not explained by virtue of the composition or interaction of more basic elements in a derivative way.
Although the ontological question must be raised, instead of a duality in this case, we can talk about a three-way relationship - first, with the mind as a thinking, active entity (with the modes of understanding and will); then with the extended bodies, which are knowable by the imagination and whose unity resides in an external, contingent principle; and finally, with the experience of my body as passively thinking flesh, where the union of the mind with its modalities of imagination, sensation and passion are inextricably linked with corporeality, whose principle of essential unity is the indivisible mind, and which guarantees and at the same time sustains itself thanks to the functional unity of the organism.57
How can we manage that distinction? The fact is that although it is asserted in the theoretical dimension, with special clarity in the Meditations as well as in the answers to the objections of his critics, only occasionally do we find a text of Descartes in which the thinker affirms the reality of a reflection and an affective function independent of the union between spirit and body: "All these movements of the will that constitute love, joy, sadness and desire, insofar as they are rational thoughts and not passions, could exist in our soul even if it had no body" (AT IV: 602/CSMK: 306). However, this conceptual piece is not repeated, and, in a consistent and orthodox way, Descartes refers continuously to divine omnipotence as a guarantor, incomprehensible to the human intellect but effective for the believer regarding the possible existence of spirit separated from the body - that is, of the immortality of the human soul or of the subsistence of other spiritual powers, like angels.58
It can be concluded, therefore, that although Descartes experiences significant difficulties in abandoning Aristotelian scholastic language59 and his attempts to elaborate new concepts (such as that of primitive notions) suffer from limitations, his proposal conceives of the true human being as an embodied mind, at least in the realm of life, in the practical dimension. If at the moment of theoretical and metaphysical reflection it is possible to conceive clearly and distinctly of the mind and body separately, such a distinction does not necessarily rest on a substantial dualism, and in that sense, there is no guarantee of existence or subsistence beyond thought, unless divinity allows it, but it escapes our philosophical, rational, understanding.
5. CONCLUSION
This comprehensive study of Cartesian thought, placed in its historical context and maintaining a panoramic view of his written work, allows us, at least in the realm of passion and the thorny problem of the mind-body relationship, to accept the ironic complaint that he once shared with his correspondent Chanut: "A certain Father Bourdin thought he had good reason to accuse me of being a sceptic, because I refuted the sceptics; and a certain minister tried to argue that I was an atheist, without giving any reason other than the fact that I tried to prove the existence of God" (AT IV: 536/CSMK: 299).
Without a doubt, the readings that gave rise to the Cartesian legend are due to a systematic interpretive bad faith, which attempted to discredit a complex thought by means of a decontextualizing and fragmented hermeneutic. However, our interpretation has not only challenged the popular radical dualist view (still present in the academic sphere, as evidenced by the references to Ryle and Damasio) but has also attempted to reveal, even partially, its tremendous actuality under a more careful reading.
As we indicated at the end of our introduction, the problem of consciousness, as a specific aspect of the question concerning the link between mind and body, is one of the most commonly addressed issues by philosophy from the mid-twentieth century to the present day. We recognize ourselves as conscious beings who feel, smell, taste, see and hear and who are moved to tears or laughter, but we do not know well what these feelings and emotions are.
The eminent philosopher David J. Chalmers dedicated his work, The Conscious Mind, to consider this subjective experience. There, the author considers that the great majority of our mental notions possess a dual nature - a phenomenal or experiential dimension and a psychological, causal dimension.60 While the second can be approached from the perspective of the cognitive science, the first, especially the domain of consciousness or subjective experience, is more difficult to address, since requires philosophical elucidation and engagement with epistemic and ontological questions in need of conceptual and non-experimental analysis.
In this article, we have shown that Descartes, on the one hand, against his black legend, was deeply interested in the anatomical and psychological aspects of organisms in general and in the human brain in particular. In fact, as demonstrated, he was attracted by the scientific, observational dimension of the human machine of his time. On the other hand, in line with certain research of the last decades, we have explain Descartes’ interest on the conceptual study of the mind and the emotions, highlighting his phenomenological perspective with the investigation of an inexhaustible experiential part of the passionate human being: the embodied mind.
In short, and without delving into a parallelism that conceptual and historical distances speak from, we have emphasized a re-reading of the body's role in Cartesian thought as diametrically different from the legendary Descartes that the tradition has presented to us. Italo Calvino said in a text that became an instant classic from the moment of its publication that "a classic is a book that never finishes saying what it has to say".61 We could replicate this assertion by saying that the passionate Descartes of the anatomical studies, the adventurous mechanistic hypotheses, and the risky metaphysical and psychological theses (which both distinguishes and associates science and philosophy) still has much to tell us. His actuality does not come from the (scarce) success in the specific details but from an undeniable fact despite its legend: the questions that Descartes raised and the perspective from which he formulated them remain, in some measure, ours.