Acessibilidade / Reportar erro

Appropriation, beliefs, and inculcation: Some other connections between American Pragmatism and Veblen’s conspicuous consumer* * Note: A previous version of this paper was presented at the 46th ANPEC meeting, Rio de Janeiro, December 2018. The authors thank the participants in this event. This research has been supported by the Conselho Nacional de Desenvolvimento Científico e Tecnológico (CNPq).

Apropriação, crenças e inculcação: algumas outras conexões entre o pragmatismo americano e o consumidor conspícuo de Veblen

ABSTRACT

Thorstein Veblen was a founding father of the original institutional economics. Veblen’s first book, The Theory of the Leisure Class (1899), introduced to economists an interdisciplinary perspective to understand consumers’ decision-making. This perspective relied on the processual nature of instincts, habits, and institutions. Veblen’s ideas on human behavior were not completely original, and it has been widely recognized that some of his insights clearly reference the teachings of the American pragmatic school of philosophy. In light of this, our study offers an interpretation of Veblen’s ideas on consumer behavior through the viewpoints of the main thinkers of the pragmatist school of his time. This study explores some important themes within pragmatism, such as William James’s concept of appropriation, Charles Peirce’s understanding of belief and social impulse, and John Dewey’s ideas on socialization and the inculcation of habits. Based on these references, we seek to generate new insights into Veblen’s perspective on consumers’ decision-making in broader terms and at the same time preserve his main philosophical references.

KEYWORDS:
Thorstein Veblen; conspicuous consumption; pragmatism; pragmatic philosophy; institutional economics

RESUMO

Thorstein Veblen foi um dos fundadores da economia institucional original. O primeiro livro de Veblen, The Theory of the Leisure Class (1899), apresentou aos economistas uma perspectiva interdisciplinar para compreender a tomada de decisão dos consumidores. Essa perspectiva dependia da natureza processual dos instintos, hábitos e instituições. As ideias de Veblen sobre o comportamento humano não eram completamente originais e foi amplamente reconhecido que alguns de seus insights claramente fazem referência aos ensinamentos da escola americana de filosofia pragmática. Diante disso, nosso estudo oferece uma interpretação das ideias de Veblen sobre o comportamento do consumidor por meio dos pontos de vista dos principais pensadores da escola pragmática de sua época. Este estudo explora alguns temas importantes dentro do pragmatismo, como o conceito de apropriação de William James, a compreensão de Charles Peirce sobre a crença e o impulso social e as ideias de John Dewey sobre socialização e a inculcamento de hábitos. Com base nessas referências, buscamos gerar novos insights sobre a perspectiva de Veblen em relação a tomada de decisão dos consumidores em termos mais amplos e, ao mesmo tempo, preservar suas principais referências filosóficas.

PALAVRAS-CHAVE:
Thorstein Veblen; consumo conspícuo; pragmatismo; filosofia pragmática; economia institucional

1. INTRODUCTION

One of the most important features of Thorstein Veblen’s evolutionary economics is the concept of “conspicuous consumption.” Much different from the neoclassical end-driven behavior, Veblen’s understanding of consumer behavior is culturally grounded.1 1 We must remember that Veblen (1900) coined the word “neoclassical” mainly to refer to the ideas spread by the Marginalist Revolution. For Veblen (1889) emulative behavior is a product of human history that became institutionally stable within western society in the form of conspicuous consumption. Following this, conspicuous consumption is a specific kind of consumption because it is addressed to display wealth to others, it is a massive behavior since it is “[t]he basis on which good repute in any highly organized industrial community ultimately rests” (1884). In this sense, for Veblen - and for all radical institutionalists - consumption must be seen as an interpersonal issue that moves around reputation and social hierarchy. Consequently, Veblen’s conspicuous consumer can be defined as the person who buy goods emulatively, looking for a -not necessarily consciously-wasteful monetary expenditure motivated by social esteem.

Veblen’s perspective on consumption reflects his profound interdisciplinarity since he connects the cutting edge of several disciplines of his time as psychology, philosophy, economics and social theory. From these foundations Veblen concluded that evolutionary economists must understand consumer behavior as the result of a historical process based on the dynamics grounded on instincts, habits, and institutions. The innovative nature of Veblen’s perspective might be explained by Joseph Dorfman, his first well-known biographer, through Dorfman’s “outsider thesis” (1934), which explains Veblen’s approach as the result of Veblen’s being a non-participant researcher of American socio-economic practices. Nevertheless, in the last decades, efforts have been made within Original Institutional Economics (OIE) to understand the theoretical and philosophical roots of Veblen’s thought and his connection with other thinkers of his time (Camic, 2012Camic, C. (2012). Schooling for Heterodoxy: On the Foundations of Thorstein Veblen’s Institutional Economics. In: Reinert, E and Viano, F. (2012). Thorstein Veblen: Economics for an Age of Crisis. London: Anthem Press.). Thus, several works have shown that important insights of Veblen’s social theory rely-among other areas-on the teachings of the American pragmatic school of philosophy (Edgell and Tilman, 1989Edgell, S., & Tilman, R. (1989). The intellectual antecedents of Thorstein Veblen: a reappraisal. Journal of Economic Issues , 23(4), 1003-1026.; Twomey, 1998Twomey, P. (1998). Reviving Veblenian economic psychology. Cambridge Journal of Economics , 22, 433-448.; Tilman, 2007Tilman, R. (2007). Thorstein Veblen and the Enrichment of Evolutionary Naturalism. London: University of Missouri Press. ).

Regarding the centrality of “conspicuous consumer” on Veblen’s theoretical framework and the need to understand Veblen as a thinker connected to the ideas of his time, this paper seeks to offer some insights on the possible connections between Veblen’s “conspicuous consumer” and selected themes of American pragmatism. In this sense, the reassessment of Veblen’s “conspicuous consumer” under the lights of Peirce, Dewey and James may show the deepness and breadth of Veblen’s perspective on cognition, consumption, and institutions.

When Veblen was a student at John Hopkins University, he attended Charles Peirce’s lectures for the course “Elementary Logic” during the fall of 18812 2 Peirce was a temporary lecturer at John Hopkins University from 1879 to 1884 (Liebhafsky, 1993). (Griffin, 1998Griffin, R. (1998). What Veblen owed to Peirce-the social theory of logic. Journal of Economic Issues , 32(3), 733-757.; Liebhafsky, 1993Liebhafsky, E. (1993). The influence of Charles Sanders Peirce on Institutional Economics. Journal of Economic Issues , 27(3), 741-754.; Camic, 2012Camic, C. (2012). Schooling for Heterodoxy: On the Foundations of Thorstein Veblen’s Institutional Economics. In: Reinert, E and Viano, F. (2012). Thorstein Veblen: Economics for an Age of Crisis. London: Anthem Press.). Exposure to Peirce’s lectures deeply influenced Veblen’s strong identification with evolutionary description (Dyer, 1986Dyer, A. (1986). Veblen on scientific creativity: the influence of Charles S. Peirce. Journal of Economic Issues , 20(1), 21-41.; Liebhafsky, 1993Liebhafsky, E. (1993). The influence of Charles Sanders Peirce on Institutional Economics. Journal of Economic Issues , 27(3), 741-754.). Peirce was a source for Veblen’s theory, and several Veblenian ideas have a strong association with Peirce’s pragmaticism3 3 From his 1905 paper, “What Pragmatism is?”, Peirce began to call his philosophical perspective as “pragmaticism.” This was a reaction to the bad use of the term “pragmatism,” as Peirce (1905, p. 165) states: “at present, the word begins to be met with occasionally in the literary journals, where it gets abused in the merciless way that words have to expect when they fall into literary clutches [...] So then, the writer, finding his bantling ‘pragmatism’ so promoted, feels that it is time to kiss his child good-by and relinquish it to its higher destiny; while to serve the precise purpose of expressing the original definition, he begs to announce the birth of the word ‘pragmaticism,’ which is ugly enough to be safe from kidnappers.” , such as Veblen’s concept of “idle curiosity” with Peirce’s “musement” (Dyer, 1986Dyer, A. (1986). Veblen on scientific creativity: the influence of Charles S. Peirce. Journal of Economic Issues , 20(1), 21-41.; Liebhafsky, 1993Liebhafsky, E. (1993). The influence of Charles Sanders Peirce on Institutional Economics. Journal of Economic Issues , 27(3), 741-754.) as well as the famous concept of “cumulative causation” with Peirce’s “synechism” (Hall and Whybrow, 2008Hall, J., & Whybrow, O. (2008) “Continuity and Continuousness: The Chain of Ideas Linking Peirce’s Synechism to Veblen’s Cumulative Causation.” Journal of Economic Issues , 42 (2), 349-355.). The presence of Peirce’s ideas in Veblen’s studies can be found in Kant’s Critique of Judgment (Veblen, 1884Veblen, T. (1884). Kant’s Critique of Judgment. Journal of Speculative Philosophy 18(3): 260-274), The Instinct of Workmanship and the State of the Industrial Arts (Veblen, 1914Veblen, T. (2006). [1914]. The instinct of workmanship and the state of the industrial arts. New York: Cosimo .), and in “Economic Theory in the Calculable Future” (Veblen, 1925Veblen, T. (1925). Economic theory in the calculable future. American Economic Review , 15(1), 48-55.)4 4 Veblen (1884) is essential for one to perceive Peirce’s influence on Veblen’s writings as it describes precisely Peirce’s three fundamental principles of logic: (i) the supremacy of inductive reasoning, (ii) the mediating role of human apprehension, and (iii) the power of judgment of the human mind. These principles, through which Veblen describes Kant’s work, constitute evidence toward the affinity between Peirce and Kant regarding the elaboration of scientific hypotheses. The idea that such hypotheses are the result of the mediating role of the human mind must be highlighted here as a starting point to trace the connections between Veblen’s understanding of scientific inquiry and Peirce’s conception of human logic. (Dyer, 1986Dyer, A. (1986). Veblen on scientific creativity: the influence of Charles S. Peirce. Journal of Economic Issues , 20(1), 21-41.; Griffin, 1998Griffin, R. (1998). What Veblen owed to Peirce-the social theory of logic. Journal of Economic Issues , 32(3), 733-757.).

Despite the importance of Peirce’s writings on Veblen’s theory, Mirowski (1987Mirowski, P. (1987). The philosophical bases of institutional economics. Journal of Economic Issues , 21(3), 1001-1038.) stresses that Veblen was more influenced by John Dewey than by Peirce. When Veblen attended Peirce’s lectures in the “Elementary Logic” course, he did so along with Dewey (Griffin, 1998Griffin, R. (1998). What Veblen owed to Peirce-the social theory of logic. Journal of Economic Issues , 32(3), 733-757.; Liebhafsky, 1993Liebhafsky, E. (1993). The influence of Charles Sanders Peirce on Institutional Economics. Journal of Economic Issues , 27(3), 741-754.). Peirce influenced both Veblen’s and Dewey’s philosophy and the logic of scientific thought; however, neither Veblen nor Dewey shared Peirce’s “evolutionary metaphysics,” which he developed at the beginning of the 20th century. Thereafter, from 1894 to 1904, Veblen and Dewey were colleagues at the University of Chicago; Veblen was a member of the Political Economy Department during 1892-1906, and Dewey was a member of the Philosophy Department during 1894-1904 (Rutherford, 2011Rutherford, M. (2011). The institutionalist movement in American economics, 1918-1947: science and social control. Cambridge: the Cambridge University Press.). It is unquestionable that Dewey heavily influenced Veblen’s concept of habits and evolutionary perspective. In addition, completing the pragmatist “holy trinity,” William James is well known in OIE as an important influence in Veblen’s notion of instincts (see Hodgson, 1998bHodgson, G. (1998b). On the Evolution of Thorstein Veblen’s Evolutionary Economics. Cambridge Journal of Economics , 22(4), 15-431; Jennings and Waller, 1998Jennings, A. & Waller. W. (1998). The Place of Biological Science in Veblen’s Economics. History of Political Economy, 30 (2), 189-217.), which is unusual (Almeida, 2014Almeida, F. (2014). Thorstein Veblen and Albert Bandura: a modern psychological reading of the conspicuous consumer. Journal of Economic Issues, 48(1), 109-122.). According to Hodgson (1998bHodgson, G. (1998b). On the Evolution of Thorstein Veblen’s Evolutionary Economics. Cambridge Journal of Economics , 22(4), 15-431), Veblen followed James in his approach to instincts, which he explained in terms of both biological and socio-economical processes of evolution (see also Almeida, 2014Almeida, F. (2014). Thorstein Veblen and Albert Bandura: a modern psychological reading of the conspicuous consumer. Journal of Economic Issues, 48(1), 109-122.). Following these efforts to ground Veblen’s ideas on earthly philosophical foundations, this study seeks to understand the connections between Veblen’s “conspicuous consumer” and the pragmatist conceptions of human behavior. Thus, we highlight and analyze possible theoretical bridges regarding these connections. Our study focuses on three common themes among the previously mentioned thinkers: (i) the process of habit acquisition, (ii) the nature and meaning of instincts, and (iii) the roots of human action and satisfaction. More specifically, to offer a pragmatist reference to qualify Veblen’s “conspicuous consumer” within pragmatist philosophy, our study delves into James’s appropriation, Peirce’s belief and doubt logic, and Dewey’s socialization and inculcation of habits.

The following section considers how the conspicuous consumer perceives habits and the relationship between habits and instincts. It highlights how the conspicuous consumer deals with the inner impulse to consume and the meaning of Veblen’s notion of instincts. It is argued that James’s appropriation-complemented by Dewey’s perspective on habits and socialization-plays a central role in how consumers perceive the way goods are acquired in social decision-making environments. Section 3 highlights how Peirce’s logic regarding doubts as well as beliefs in learning how to behave assist the habit-building aspect of Veblen’s conspicuous consumer. Section 4 introduces the notion of institutions in the analysis. This section explores the role of the leisure class institution in building the social concepts of goods and their relationship with habits as well as Veblen’s notion of conspicuousness. Some concluding remarks are presented in Section 5.

2. THE ROLE OF WILLIAM JAMES’S APPROPRIATION

Considering the place Veblen gave to habits in his writings, it is impossible to begin an analysis of Veblenian decision-making without mentioning Veblen’s concept of habits. The importance of habits in Veblen’s institutionalism is reinforced when we observe that two of the most quoted definitions of institutions, provided by Veblen, rely on habits: institutions as “settled habits of thought common to the generality of men” (Veblen, 1909Veblen, T. (1909). The limitations of marginal utility. Journal of Political Economy, 17(9), 620-636., p. 626) and institutions as outgrowths of habits (Veblen, 1909Veblen, T. (1909). The limitations of marginal utility. Journal of Political Economy, 17(9), 620-636., 1919Veblen, T. (2005) [1919]. The vested interests and the common man. New York: Cosimo .). Hodgson (1998aHodgson, G. (1998a). The approach of institutional economics. Journal of Economic Literature, 36, 166-192. ) understands the Veblenian concept of habit as a largely non-deliberative and self-actuating propensity to engage in a previously adopted pattern. A key issue in understanding conspicuous consumers’ decision-making is to comprehend how that pattern is recognized, learned, and adopted. To this end, to fully understand this subject, a reference to William James’s and John Dewey’s writings might be useful.

In The Theory of the Leisure Class (Veblen, 1899Veblen, T. (2007) [1899]. The Theory of the Leisure Class. Oxford: Oxford University Press.), Veblen analyzed the impact of socially shared habits on conspicuous consumer decision-making. Here, we retreat a few steps, examining how Veblen’s conspicuous consumer acquires such habits. Thus, it is important to understand how to handle the concept of habit. Here, we differentiate between “being aware of what a habit is” and “what a habit means.” The former relies on knowing how to put a habit in practice, such as knowing what the usual meal in a specific country is and how to have access to this meal. “What a habit means” is about understanding what the habit expresses, such as comprehending the cultural content of the usual meal in a specific country. Veblen’s conspicuous consumer theory is about “being aware of what a habit is” and about “what a habit means.” Initially, we focus on the former in this section, whereas Section 4 considers the meaning of a habit.

It may be argued that the conspicuous consumer is aware of a habit when she/he notices its behavioral results. Following this logic, a habit is perceived when it is implied by one’s behavior. However, from a Veblenian perspective, a habit does not refer to repetitive behavior. A habit can be seen as a potential behavior that can be triggered by an appropriate stimulus or context (Hodgson, 2002Hodgson, G. (2002). The evolution of institutions: an agenda for future theoretical research. Constitutional Political Economy, 13(2), 111-127. , 2004bHodgson, G. (2004b). Reclaiming habit for institutional economics. Journal of Economic Psychology, 25: 651-660. ). In addition, a habit is not necessarily implied by one’s behavior because a habit can also be associated with the absence of a behavior5 5 For example, to acquire the habit of a healthy life suggests denying several types of behaviors, such as smoking, eating greasy food, and drinking beer on a daily basis. However, the habit of a healthy life also suggests participating in sports, eating fruit and vegetables, and drinking water regularly as desirable types of behavior. The habit of a healthy life as described here offers an illustration of behaviors that can and cannot imply a habit. This example does not illustrate Veblenian habits in a general sense, because not necessarily being implied by a behavior is only one feature of Veblenian habits. Later on, we consider the other features of habits according to Veblen. . However, when the subject matter is “being aware of what a habit is,” a habit’s behavioral result plays a key role, even when this behavioral result is the absence of a behavior. As the analysis of habits that are implied or not implied by behavior is similar, we will henceforth focus on habits that culminate in behavior.

The concept of being aware of a habit’s behavioral results guides our discussion toward the reasons why consumers engage in certain behaviors. There are certainly several reasons that motivate a consumer to behave in a certain way. If we focus on basic motivation for behavior, philosophers and psychologists usually indicate instincts as behavioral incentives. Veblen introduces his own perspective of an instinctive approach, which is central to comprehending the logic of his conspicuous consumer. A key issue in Veblen’s approach to instinct is the unusual perspective he adopted. For Veblen (1914Veblen, T. (2006). [1914]. The instinct of workmanship and the state of the industrial arts. New York: Cosimo .), inner impulses to action are tropisms or reflexes; philosophers and psychologists usually use the term instinct for what Veblen called tropism or reflex. In addition, Veblen used the term instinct differently from its usual sense. According to Veblen, cognitive abilities, particular perceptions, and even intelligence are part of instincts (Cordes, 2005Cordes, C. (2005). Veblen’s “Instinct of Workmanship,” its cognitive foundations, and some implications for economic theory. Journal of Economic Issues , 39(1), 1-20.). Consequently, the Veblenian perspective of instincts takes into account the relationship between consumers and the external world around them, which differs from the common-sense or usual conceptualization. For Veblen, what is learned in one’s interaction with the external world can create an instinct. To avoid a conceptual confusion, the term “instinct” is used here as defined by Veblen. The usual meaning of conceptualization is termed “inner impulse.” Notably, William James’s writings, particularly his notion of appropriation, are central to an in-depth analysis of Veblen’s concept of instinct and its relation with habits.

James’s notion of appropriation is interrelated with other important elements of his thought. First, we consider that, although James’s notion of habit is compatible with Veblen’s, James’s is a more encompassing concept. As understood by James, the concept of habit is well beyond human phenomena since according to him, “[t]he laws of Nature are nothing but the immutable habits, which the different elementary sorts of matter follow in their actions and reactions upon each other” (James 1890aJames, W. (2007) [originally published 1890a]. The principles of psychology: volume 1. New York: Cosimo., p. 104). In line with his concept of habit, James dealt with another concept named plasticity: “[p]lasticity, […], in the wide sense of the word, means the possession of a structure weak enough to yield to an influence but strong enough not to yield all at once. Each relatively stable phase of equilibrium in such a structure is marked by what we may call a new set of habits” (James, 1890aJames, W. (2007) [originally published 1890a]. The principles of psychology: volume 1. New York: Cosimo., p. 105).

In this sense, we may assume that plasticity and habits are different but related phenomena, as habits refer to a stable set of known behaviors and plasticity means the flexibility that allows a new set of behaviors to be learned. Taking decision-making into account, being aware of a habit means knowing its behavioral results and plasticity means the learning process of how to behave. However, this learning process, despite creating new habits, may also reinforce the existing ones. When a reinforcement takes place, the reinforced habit becomes a stronger structure that, through the same process, can become strong enough to have the same impact on the conspicuous consumer as an inner impulse. For James, a habit that is strong enough to work as an inner impulse is an instinct. In James’s words, “[t]he habits to which there is an innate tendency are called instincts” (James 1890aJames, W. (2007) [originally published 1890a]. The principles of psychology: volume 1. New York: Cosimo., p. 104). Hence, we can assume that James understood that inner impulses could be subsumed within habits. This is very close to Veblen’s perspective on instincts as a category that encompasses inner impulses and elements of the external world, which in Veblenian theory are expressed as habits.

If we understand a habit as the procedure determining how one behaves and plasticity as the learning process, then we need a theory of change that links both concepts. James offered this theory while exploring the concept of “appropriation.” In our view, James’s appropriation is central to understanding Veblen’s conspicuous consumer decision-making. To introduce the appropriation process, James (1904James, W. (1904). Does ‘Consciousness’ Exist? The Journal of Philosophy Psychology and Scientific Methods. 1(18), 477-491., 1905James, W. (1905). How Two Minds Can Know One Thing. The Journal of Philosophy Psychology and Scientific Methods . 2(7), 176-181.) presents consciousness as a function of “pure experience.” In this sense, for James, knowing becomes a result of “pure experience” since “[there is] only one primal stuff or material in the world, a stuff of which everything is composed, and if we call that stuff ‘pure experience,’ the knowing can easily be explained as a particular sort of relation towards one another, into which portions of pure experience may enter” (James, 1904James, W. (1904). Does ‘Consciousness’ Exist? The Journal of Philosophy Psychology and Scientific Methods. 1(18), 477-491., p. 478).

Any content of “pure experience”-such as consuming a good-must be classed as a physical entity and as a perception of the mind so it must assume both functions. The differences between these two functions are radical. We can illustrate this by associating “pure experience” with a simple good, such as a pen, an example provided by James himself: “[s]o far as [a pen] in the world is a stable feature, holds ink, marks paper, and obeys the guidance of a hand, it is a physical pen. That is what we mean by being ‘physical, ’ in a pen. So far, it is instable, on the contrary, coming and going with the movements of my eyes, altering with what I call my fancy, continuous with subsequent experiences of its ‘having been’ (in the past tense), it is the precept of a pen in my mind. Those peculiarities are what we mean by being ‘conscious,’ in a pen” (1905, p. 177).

The perception of “pure experience” in our mind occurs through appropriation, that is, a process where earlier experiences that are already in decision-makers’ minds accommodate new experiences. Hence, “pure experience” is accommodated in decision-making through plasticity, therefore, defining plasticity as a part of the appropriation process. Regarding Veblen’s understanding of the conspicuous consumer, we might say that the habits of the external world already internalized by the conspicuous consumer-which can be instincts-constitute the plasticity of new habits to come. The difference between internalized habits or instincts and “pure experiences” that have not (yet) been lived creates the separation between what is the decision-maker’s mind and what is part of the external world. It is an anti-cartesian perspective because it is not an ontological separation. Instead, it is a perceptive separation: what the consumer perceives that is a part of her/his decision-making vs. what she/he perceives as not being a part of her/his decision-making.

There is a key subject related to habits and inner impulses that should be given significant attention in the analysis of consumption, namely, an inner impulse generates a robust motivation to behave and, by behaving, consumers must interact with what allows behavior to take place. An inner impulse is an internal and personal force but to behave in line with this force, consumers should deal with goods-which work as “pure experience.” Simply by consuming goods, consumers can make inner impulses stop pressuring them to behave in a certain way. Removing the pressure to consume is the basis for consumer satisfaction.6 6 This sentence may suggest that the only source of satisfaction for a consumer is the end of her/his inner impulses’ pressure to consume but this is quite wrong from Veblen’s perspective. According to Veblen (1899), institutional pressures are important pressures a consumer must attend to so as to be satisfied. This issue is introduced later in this section and further emphasized in subsequent sections. In addition, since this study references satisfaction as a result of an inner impulse, it is important to highlight that Veblen rejects the utilitarian pleasure-pain decision-making logic (Argyrous and Sethi, 1996; Veblen, 1898, 1909). The passage below is usually quoted in the context of strong disapproval of the traditional economics-based approach to decision-making: “The hedonistic conception of man is that of a lightning calculator of pleasures and pains, who oscillates like a homogeneous globule of desire of happiness under the impulse of stimuli that shift him about the area but leave him intact. He has neither antecedent nor consequent. He is an isolated, definitive human datum, in stable equilibrium except for the buffets of the impinging forces that displace him in one direction or another … The later psychology, re-enforced by modern anthropological research, gives a different conception of human nature. According to this conception, it is the characteristic of man to do something, not simply to suffer pleasures and pains through the impact of suitable forces. He is not simply a bundle of desires that are to be saturated by being placed in the path of the forces of the environment, but rather a coherent structure of propensities and habits which seeks realization and expression in an unfolding activity” (Veblen, 1898, pp. 389-390).Veblen believed that an individualistic pleasure-pain reading of human behavior is not enough. From a Veblenian perspective, the socialization process adds other layers to decision-making. This study further clarifies this point.

As we can extrapolate from James (1890bJames, W. (2007) [originally published in 1890b]. The principles of psychology: volume 2. New York: Cosimo ., 1904James, W. (1904). Does ‘Consciousness’ Exist? The Journal of Philosophy Psychology and Scientific Methods. 1(18), 477-491., 1905James, W. (1905). How Two Minds Can Know One Thing. The Journal of Philosophy Psychology and Scientific Methods . 2(7), 176-181.), relationships between inner impulses and goods are built according to an appropriation process. Through this process, consumers learn how to connect goods to inner impulses so they can attend the latter and alleviate pressure. As we saw above, appropriation is not related to the essence of inner impulses. Appropriation, in the consumer’s case, is the process of connecting inner impulses and goods. It is a way to secure the satisfaction generated by eliminating an impulse to behave in a certain way by behaving in that way (James, 1890bJames, W. (2007) [originally published in 1890b]. The principles of psychology: volume 2. New York: Cosimo ., p. 423). Hence, it is possible to argue that appropriation means that there is an impulse-good connection. This connection does not exist from the beginning and can change over time or can be rigidly fixed because it is mediated by plasticity. It is a matter of how consumers learn to put their inner impulses into practice-it is a matter of a habit.7 7 James (1890b) emphasizes that human beings’ motivation to behave in a certain way is like that of any other creature, and human beings’ inner impulses are as “blind” as those of other creatures.

For Dewey (1921Dewey, J. (1921). Human nature and conduct: an introduction to social psychology. New York: DC Heath & Co Publishers .), the blindness of inner impulses does not create a problem with decision-making because inner impulses become organized into almost any behavioral disposition. As stated above, this organization of inner impulses into disposition takes place through the appropriation process. Hence, such dispositions are learned through the interactions of the consumer with the world around her/him (see Dewey, 1910aDewey, J. (1910a). How we think, New York: DC Heath & Co Publishers., 1921Dewey, J. (1921). Human nature and conduct: an introduction to social psychology. New York: DC Heath & Co Publishers .). Indeed, James (1890bJames, W. (2007) [originally published in 1890b]. The principles of psychology: volume 2. New York: Cosimo .) stresses that appropriation is associated with the habitualization of how one puts impulses into practice, that is, how one creates or supports an impulse-good connection. James (1890bJames, W. (2007) [originally published in 1890b]. The principles of psychology: volume 2. New York: Cosimo .) adds a key idea to follow this logic, namely, that habits can inhibit inner impulses: “[a] habit, once grafted on an instinctive tendency, restricts the range of the tendency itself, and keeps us from reacting on any but the habitual object […]” (James, 1890bJames, W. (2007) [originally published in 1890b]. The principles of psychology: volume 2. New York: Cosimo ., p. 395) and “[i]n civilized life the impulse to own is usually checked by a variety of considerations, and only passes over into action under circumstances legitimated by habit and common consent” (James, 1890bJames, W. (2007) [originally published in 1890b]. The principles of psychology: volume 2. New York: Cosimo ., p. 422).

Dewey (1921Dewey, J. (1921). Human nature and conduct: an introduction to social psychology. New York: DC Heath & Co Publishers ., p. 125) contributes to this discussion by affirming that: “Man is a creature of habit, not of reason nor yet of instinct [inner impulse].” This relationship between inner impulses and habits reinforces the idea in Veblen’s approach, that there are no “pure impulses” but rather habits built under the influence of one’s association with others who already hold habits (the evolution of habits in a society relies on this logic). The use of such a concept of habits is a strong influence of Dewey on Veblen. Dewey is emphatic in his definition of habit: “[…] we must protest against the tendency in psychological literature to limit its meaning to repetition” (Dewey, 1921Dewey, J. (1921). Human nature and conduct: an introduction to social psychology. New York: DC Heath & Co Publishers ., p. 41).8 8 For Dewey (1921), repetition is not even the essence of habit. However, repetition can be an incident of many habits. An individual looking for a healthier life provides an example of a habit that is not associated with repetition. Foregoing sugar, fatty food, and smoking can be habits acquired by the individual. These habits do not imply repetitive behavior. For Dewey (1921), the essence of a habit is a predisposition to ways or modes of behavior. A habit means special sensitivity or accessibility to certain classes of stimuli.

Regarding Veblen’s notion of instincts, it is important to highlight that appropriation is already part of instincts. From Veblen’s perspective, instincts are composed not only of inner impulses but also of impulse-good connections.9 9 Veblen stresses some types of instinct. The main types are the instinct of workmanship, parental bent, and idle curiosity. However, given the goal of this study, Veblen’s specific types of instinct are not central to the analysis. The central issue is Veblen’s perspective on instincts and the manner in which they can influence consumer decision-making. For more information about the instinct of workmanship, parental bent, and idle curiosity, see Latsis (2009). An essential point regarding Veblen’s conspicuous consumer is that impulse-good connections are social issues. Consequently, satisfaction is also a social issue in Veblen’s analysis. Dewey (1921Dewey, J. (1921). Human nature and conduct: an introduction to social psychology. New York: DC Heath & Co Publishers ., p. 89) highlights this logic, affirming that “[i]mpulses although first in time are never primary in fact; they are secondary and dependent,” as other people show consumers how to deal with the external world. “The meaning of native activities is not native; it is acquired” (Dewey, 1921Dewey, J. (1921). Human nature and conduct: an introduction to social psychology. New York: DC Heath & Co Publishers ., p. 90). At the end of this process, they are socially created habits.

The pragmatist philosophical foundation offers interesting insights into how socially created habits generate the logic of the conspicuous consumer. Among pragmatist contributions, Peirce’s logic of doubt-belief constitutes an important reference for this discussion, which will be explored in the next section.

3. CHARLES PEIRCE’S BELIEFS AND DOUBTS

The continuity or even the compatibility between James and Dewey’s version of pragmatism and Charles Peirce’s perspective is highly disputed. Although James indicated Peirce as the founder of pragmatism, the last developments of Peirce’s thought, encompassed by his evolutionary metaphysics, were very different from James and Dewey’s philosophy. Two of Peirce’s papers, “The Fixation of Belief” (1877) and “How to Make Our Ideas Clear” (1878), are known, as James (1898) indicated, as the works that founded pragmatism.10 10 Apel (1967, p. 54) indicates that Peirce (1877, 1878) expressed the ideas of Peirce’s earlier works: “Peirce had in fact already rather distinctly formulated the point that he later, for clarification, termed the ‘pragmatic maxim,’ before the discussions in the Metaphysical Club (winter 1871 to winter 1872). He did this, for example, in a passage in the 1869 essay, but the point was particularly unmistakable in the Berkeley review of 1871.” Conversely, in a series of three papers published in The Monist in 1905, Peirce explicitly separated his ideas from those of other pragmatists and even created a new name for his philosophical standpoint (Apel, 1967Apel, Karl (1967). Charles S. Peirce: From Pragmatism to Pragmaticism. Amhrest: University of Massachusetts Press. , pp. 81-83). From the perspective of the history of ideas, we must emphasize that any work aiming to offer a pragmatist perspective on a specific subject, as ours, needs to clarify this late separation between Peirce’s pragmatism and the ideas propagated through the works of James and Dewey.11 11 Our reference to Peirce’s ideas reflects this complicated relation with James and Dewey’s perspective. From a complementary viewpoint, our main references are exactly the foundational writings of the pragmatist school, that is, Peirce (1877) and Peirce (1878). Subsequently, we will restrict our analysis to the ideas of the “young Peirce.”

In Peirce (1877Peirce, C. (1877). The fixation of belief. In S. Haack, & R. Lane. (2006). Pragmatism, old & new (pp. 107-126). New York: Prometheus Books .), we find two central concepts of his theory of inquiry: belief and doubt. The belief-doubt theory was first created by the psychologist Alexander Bain (1818-1930), whose ideas were initially propagated within the Metaphysical Club and its members by the jurist Nicolas St. John Green12 12 The Metaphysical Club was a conversational group from 1871 to 1872, formed in Cambridge, Massachusetts, by Oliver Wendell Holmes Jr., William James, Charles Sanders Peirce, Chauncey Wright, John Fiske, Francis Ellingwood Abbot, Nicholas St. John Green, and Joseph Bangs Warner. . According to Bain (1859Bain, A. (1859). The Emotions and the Will. New York. D. Appleton & Company. ), belief is defined as “essentially related to Action, that is, volition […] Preparedness to act upon what we affirm is admitted on all hands to be the sole, the genuine, the unmistakable criterion of belief.” Peirce (1877Peirce, C. (1877). The fixation of belief. In S. Haack, & R. Lane. (2006). Pragmatism, old & new (pp. 107-126). New York: Prometheus Books .) absorbed this definition and expressed belief as a disposition to behave according to a conviction in the results that a specific belief entails. On the other hand, genuine doubt arises from the interruption of belief and the emergence of a sensation of irritation of the mind. According to Bain (1859Bain, A. (1859). The Emotions and the Will. New York. D. Appleton & Company. ), doubt is a state of mind “of discomfort in most cases, and sometimes of the most aggravated wretchedness.”

Influenced by Darwin’s discussion on social feelings in animals and humans (Darwin, 1872Darwin, C. (1872). The expression of the emotions in man and animals. London: John Murray.), Peirce indicated that human beings naturally tend to search for an agreement with the widest possible community. As social animals, humans are naturally inclined to resolve the disagreements among them, to move from fragmentation and conflict toward conformity, a behavior that he termed “social impulse.”13 13 It is important to note that Peirce’s perspective is rooted in Chauncey Wright’s philosophy, which combined positivist ideas with evolutionary Darwinism. In “Evolution of Self-Consciousness” (1873), Wright established a continuity line between animal instincts and human intelligence based on the role of adaptive behavior throughout history (see also Apel, 1967, pp. 56-57). Social impulse explains the social character of belief from Peirce’s perspective.14 14 It is important to indicate that the belief-doubt theory establishes the behavioral support of Peirce’s evolutionary philosophy. Peirce (1877) presents and criticizes three different methods that the human mind appeals to for fixing a belief. The first method is called “the method of tenacity” and refers to how the human mind is inclined to keep the beliefs it already has established, or defend these beliefs as a “steady and immovable faith,” and reject whatever beliefs it has already rejected. The second method is called “the method of authority” and refers to the moment when organizations and their institutions establish beliefs in human minds, as has happened in several moments in human history: “[t]his method has, from the earliest times, been more of the chief means of upholding correct theological and political doctrines, and of preserving their universal or catholic character […] Wherever there is an aristocracy, or a guild, or any association of a class of men whose interests depend, or are supposed to depend, on certain propositions, there will be inevitably some traces of this natural product of social feeling.” The third method is the Cartesian “a priori method,” where beliefs become firm because the propositions in question are guaranteed by the light of reason (implanted by God in our minds), which is independent of individual perspective or the institutional environment. For Peirce (1877), these three methods for forming a belief all have the same problem: they ignore an important evolutionary trace in human nature, “social impulse.” Human beings share beliefs as a way to handle doubt; it is an evolutionary feature that connects the psychological perspective of human behavior to a social conception of logic (Fitzgerald, 1968Fitzgerald, J. (1968). Peirce’s Theory of Inquiry. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society. 4(3), 130-143.).15 15 This behavioral disposition is the main support for Peirce’s “fallibilist” understanding of the logic of science. For more information, we refer the reader to Margolis (1998).

Based on this short description of the connection between Peirce’s concepts of belief and doubt, we can already establish some insights to understand conspicuous consumers’ decision-making. In Section 2, we stressed that, to achieve the satisfaction of being free from an inner impulse to behave in a certain way, a consumer acquires goods. The procedure through which consumers build their acquisition of goods relies on appropriation. Appropriation connects inner impulses to goods, assisted by habits, and building instincts (in a Veblenian sense). We can find a missing link in our analysis, which this section intends to clarify. For Veblen, institutions are matters of the decision-making environment, composed of established “habits of thought common to the generality of men” (Veblen, 1909Veblen, T. (1909). The limitations of marginal utility. Journal of Political Economy, 17(9), 620-636., p. 626). Our missing link is an explanation of how elements of the external world become part of conspicuous consumer decision-making, that is, how conspicuous consumers, in fact, acquire habits.

To clarify the missing link, we must consider that a decision-making environment is composed of generalized habits. This decision-making environment is perceived by consumers through the behavior of others. People learn how to put their inner impulses into practice by understanding others’ behavioral disposition since there is a social impulse that promotes conformity. Thus, when one experiences some difficulty in decision-making, observation is the first step to deal with this difficulty (see Dewey, 1910aDewey, J. (1910a). How we think, New York: DC Heath & Co Publishers.). Other people introduce consumers to possible paths of behavior by offering up for observation their appropriation and consequent impulse-goods connections. Through observation, goods are introduced, directly or indirectly, by people other than the consumer, who deal with the same or a similar impulse to behave in a certain way. Extrapolating Peirce’s perspective on human logic, we can say that consumers observe others in the same decision-making environment and can associate beliefs and doubts with observed behavior (Peirce, 1877Peirce, C. (1877). The fixation of belief. In S. Haack, & R. Lane. (2006). Pragmatism, old & new (pp. 107-126). New York: Prometheus Books .). For Peirce (1877Peirce, C. (1877). The fixation of belief. In S. Haack, & R. Lane. (2006). Pragmatism, old & new (pp. 107-126). New York: Prometheus Books .), the possibilities to learn how to behave rely on one’s beliefs or doubts associated with what is observed.

When a consumer observes a behavior and comprehends it as one which should be adopted for her/him to be free from the impulse to consume, a belief is established-relating the consumer’s impulse to behave in a certain way to the good consumed by the person being observed. A belief can be understood as the first step in the appropriation process, which culminates in the establishment of an impulse-good connection. Consequently, the core of a belief is the notion that an inner impulse to consume would be satisfied by the consumption of a specific good. If a belief is established, the observed person becomes a model of behavior. However, beliefs are not the only result of observing the consumption of others; a consumer can also end up finding doubts through the same process.

A doubt occurs if the consumer perceives that there is no connection between what is observed and what she/he understands as the good that frees her/him from the impulse to consume. Hence, from the consumer’s perspective, a doubt means it is not possible to establish the instinct-good connection of appropriation16 16 Returning to our example of healthy life habits, a consumer may identify a bodybuilder as someone whose behavior should be classified as healthy. Hence, the bodybuilder is identified as a model of behavior and a belief is established. On the other hand, a consumer looking to establish healthy habits may view bodybuilders as athletes. Therefore, a bodybuilder would not be a model of behavior because the consumer does not desire to be an athlete but simply wants to be healthy. Consequently, doubts occur through non-identification with a model of behavior. . No belief or doubt remains strictly firm over time, due to plasticity. Hence, through time, a belief can become a doubt17 17 Let us suppose that a consumer identifies a bodybuilder as a model of behavior associated with healthy habits. Hence, the consumer builds beliefs that rely on impulse-good connections, such as a carbohydrate-rich diet. However, when the consumer starts such a diet, she/he may perceive that it is not as healthy as she/he believed. Consequently, the belief becomes a doubt. . On the other hand, if a potential belief is found, the consumer may adopt it. Doubts generate irritation and beliefs imply satisfaction (this satisfaction relies on the establishment of the appropriation, an impulse-good connection). According to Peirce (1877Peirce, C. (1877). The fixation of belief. In S. Haack, & R. Lane. (2006). Pragmatism, old & new (pp. 107-126). New York: Prometheus Books ., p. 113), “[o]ur beliefs guide our desires and shape our actions.” The irritation of doubt relies on ignorance regarding how to channelize inner impulses to behave in a certain way; in other words, there is no impulse-good connection. This irritation generates a struggle to establish beliefs (Peirce, 1877Peirce, C. (1877). The fixation of belief. In S. Haack, & R. Lane. (2006). Pragmatism, old & new (pp. 107-126). New York: Prometheus Books .)18 18 In our example, the consumer continues to search for behaviors associated with healthy habits but becomes irritated by the failure to find such behaviors. . The disturbance generated by doubts culminates in the tendency of decision-makers to be attached to beliefs (Peirce, 1877Peirce, C. (1877). The fixation of belief. In S. Haack, & R. Lane. (2006). Pragmatism, old & new (pp. 107-126). New York: Prometheus Books .).

The irritation of doubts motivates the fixation of beliefs. Through interaction with others, a potential belief can not only be found but also reviewed. During the observation process, through which consumers adopt beliefs, beliefs can be replaced, reviewed, or reinforced19 19 Dewey (1910a) introduces consumers’ thoughts into this logic. For Dewey (1910a), thought is usually associated with beliefs, which rely on some evidence or testimony. Thoughts constitute beliefs that rely on some basis, usually an observational one (Dewey, 1910a). A thought can be a supposition that can establish a belief, transform a belief into a doubt, or reinforce a belief. According to Peirce (1878, p. 132), “[…] the production of belief is the sole function of thought.” According to Peirce (1892), there are three sources of one’s developing thoughts: (1) the formation of habits based on beliefs, (2) the abandonment up of habits due to doubts, and (3) the combination of different beliefs resulting in a new variation. The combination of different beliefs develop according to Darwinian evolution (Peirce, 1892, p. 257). The combination of (1) and (2) implies that beliefs are changed by doubts. When a belief is questionable, there is a struggle between the belief and the doubt about it. James (1906) reinforces this point by highlighting that consumers’ experiences offer ways to build a behavioral process that generates the possibility for substituting a belief. . Any belief that does not result in satisfaction is questioned by a doubt and can be later rejected. The rejection of a belief takes place because a doubt is created in its place. The doubt ends when another belief is established (Peirce, 1877Peirce, C. (1877). The fixation of belief. In S. Haack, & R. Lane. (2006). Pragmatism, old & new (pp. 107-126). New York: Prometheus Books .). The result of such a process is the continuation of the doubt or the creation of a new belief. A belief may remain for a long time; however, in this case, the belief offers satisfaction to the consumer over time, reinforced by plasticity. The continuous satisfaction implies a reinforcement of the belief. When a belief is reinforced, the relevant behavior is more likely to recur. According to James (1890aJames, W. (2007) [originally published 1890a]. The principles of psychology: volume 1. New York: Cosimo.), any sequence of behavior that is frequently repeated tends to be preserved. Hence, a reinforced belief implies a behavior that is widespread in a society. In this case, models of behavior that inhabit the social environment establish a reference for consumers, who seek to behave accordingly. In this process, some consumers succeed in establishing a belief and their behavior becomes a model itself. As a consequence, there is a tendency of existing models to be reinforced in a snowball effect.

This snowball effect of models means that beliefs are disseminated in a society and establish the logic of a behavior in a consumer’s decision-making, which is the basis of habits. According to Peirce (1877Peirce, C. (1877). The fixation of belief. In S. Haack, & R. Lane. (2006). Pragmatism, old & new (pp. 107-126). New York: Prometheus Books ., 1878Peirce, C. (1878). How to make our ideas clear. In S. Haack, & R. Lane. (2006). Pragmatism, old & new (pp. 127-150). New York: Prometheus Books .), a belief is the nature of a habit, and the establishment of a habit is the essence of a belief. As a belief is introduced by others, this explicitly reveals that the habitualization of a belief is a social issue. The habitualization of a belief functions as a guiding principle for behavior (Peirce, 1877Peirce, C. (1877). The fixation of belief. In S. Haack, & R. Lane. (2006). Pragmatism, old & new (pp. 107-126). New York: Prometheus Books .): once it works, it may work again in the same or a very similar scenario. Peirce (1877Peirce, C. (1877). The fixation of belief. In S. Haack, & R. Lane. (2006). Pragmatism, old & new (pp. 107-126). New York: Prometheus Books .) reinforces this argument by highlighting that the logic of individualistic trial and error is not the procedure through which a consumer learns how to behave; it is social learning. A behavior that occurs in a society is always shared (Dewey, 1910bDewey, J. (1910b). The experimental theory of knowledge. In J. McDermott (1981). The Philosophy of John Dewey (pp. 175-193). Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press.). In Dewey’s words: “[i]t is not an ethical ‘ought’ that conduct should be social. It is social, whether bad or good” (Dewey, 1921Dewey, J. (1921). Human nature and conduct: an introduction to social psychology. New York: DC Heath & Co Publishers ., p. 17, emphasis in the original).

In summary, in our analysis, inner impulses are converted to behavior through consumers’ socialization. Such behavior relies on the observation of others’ behavior, which, in turn, becomes a belief. A belief is the first step for the consumer to build an appropriation or a relationship between an inner impulse-an internal motivation to consume-and a good. The generalization of beliefs in a society culminates in habits spreading socially in the form of institutions.

The role of beliefs and the appropriation process based on this logic is a pragmatic philosophical reading of Veblen’s conspicuous consumer. Here, beliefs are inserted in the analysis to better comprehend the logic of conspicuous consumers and, consequently, the emergence of institutions. Veblen himself theorizes about instincts, habits, and institutions. Section 2 emphasized the discussion on instincts, and this section highlighted how social habits become part of consumers’ logic. Institutions are the focus of Section 4, which explains the larger role of the Veblenian notion of conspicuous consumption in the analysis and presents Dewey’s notion of inculcation.

4. HABITS, INSTITUTIONS, THE CONCEPT OF GOODS, AND INCULCATION

The connection between instincts, habits and institutions is the central feature of institutionalist and pragmatist perspective on human behavior. Moreover, putting emphasis on the plasticity of instincts, our perspective on consumer behavior offers a different perspective on the biological importance of instincts (as inner impulse). The Pragmatist and Institutionalist reading of consumer behavior is much more grounded on the habitual and institutional nature of inner impulse when compared to perspectives the highlights “tropisms” or “reflexes” as a stable instinctive foundation.20 20 See Hodgson (1998b) and Hodgson (2004b) for an alternative perspective. Dewey (1921Dewey, J. (1921). Human nature and conduct: an introduction to social psychology. New York: DC Heath & Co Publishers .) reinforces the arguments addressed above by stressing that the necessity for cooperation between the consumer’s inner elements and the environment is central to understanding the place of habits in decision-making. This cooperation is successful when the inner impulses to consume are satisfied. However, Dewey (1921Dewey, J. (1921). Human nature and conduct: an introduction to social psychology. New York: DC Heath & Co Publishers .) also offers additional contributions to our analysis by affirming that habits not only assist the satisfaction of inner impulses-in the sense used in this study-but also create other impulses to behave in a certain way (to consume in our analysis). Hence, there are inner impulses and social (habitual) impulses to consume. A key issue for Veblen, as previously highlighted, is that social impulses and inner impulses overlap. Habits, as stated by Veblen, manifest themselves through the association of the environment with inner impulses, but habits are not reduced to this association alone. Habits hold motivators of behavior that are not related to inner impulse motivations. In short, because of inner impulses, consumers acquire socially generalized habits, and by acquiring those habits, they also acquire new motivations to consume.

Following this standpoint, Dewey (1910aDewey, J. (1910a). How we think, New York: DC Heath & Co Publishers.) affirms that habits are interactions of elements in the make-up of a decision-maker with elements from the biased traditions of the external world. Habits are influence of past knowledge on current knowledge in such a manner that the past is a condition, but it does not determine the present decision-making. However, habits inculcate in decision-makers’ minds a way to understand the external world, and concepts are inculcated in decision-making by habits (Dewey, 1910aDewey, J. (1910a). How we think, New York: DC Heath & Co Publishers.). It is not a repressive process but a learning process which relies on appropriation and plasticity. Socially established ideas, including the ideas regarding goods and their execution (i.e., acquiring a specific kind of good), rely on habits and what they can inculcate (see Peirce, 1878Peirce, C. (1878). How to make our ideas clear. In S. Haack, & R. Lane. (2006). Pragmatism, old & new (pp. 127-150). New York: Prometheus Books .; Dewey, 1921Dewey, J. (1921). Human nature and conduct: an introduction to social psychology. New York: DC Heath & Co Publishers .). Biased tradition and past knowledge manifest themselves in institutions, and their association with habits relies on the habit-institution relationship (as stated in Veblen’s social theory). Consequently, the fixation of a belief by habitualization occurs when the standard tradition contained in an institution is accepted by the thoughts of the decision-maker (Peirce, 1877Peirce, C. (1877). The fixation of belief. In S. Haack, & R. Lane. (2006). Pragmatism, old & new (pp. 107-126). New York: Prometheus Books .).

A key issue concerning habits is that they demand a certain kind of behavior, but behavior can be associated with certain kinds of interests that are inculcated in consumers’ decision-making (Peirce, 1877Peirce, C. (1877). The fixation of belief. In S. Haack, & R. Lane. (2006). Pragmatism, old & new (pp. 107-126). New York: Prometheus Books .). According to Veblen, these interests differ from the necessity of the consumer to satisfy inner impulses. Such necessities are social and presented by institutions (put into practice by conspicuous consumers through behavior according to habits). Habits and institutions carry images, feelings, conceptions, or other representations that can be used as a sign by the decision-maker. Taking consumption into account, attachments are usually associated with the concepts of goods. In an institutionalized world, appropriation is not objectively associated with the connection between an inner impulse to consume and a good to satisfy this impulse. The association relies on a socially built meaning of a good, an institutionalized concept of a good.

In a decision-making environment composed of institutions, the result of a search to satisfy inner impulses occurs through the role of institutionalized procedures in consumers’ decision-making. Consequently, appropriation relies on a connection between inner impulses and the concepts of goods. The latter are shared and learned collectively through habits and institutions; any good present in a modern society is attached to an institutionally shared meaning. That is why habits and institutions are stronger than inner impulses in Veblen’s decision-making approach. For Peirce (1868Peirce, C. (1868). Some consequences of four incapacities. In S. Haack, & R. Lane. (2006). Pragmatism, old & new (pp. 69-105). New York: Prometheus Books .), a conceptualization is a state of mind that carries a meaning and logical understanding. This understanding must be consistent regarding the concept of a good and what this concept generates for the consumer, namely, satisfaction-social satisfaction.

Veblen (1899Veblen, T. (2007) [1899]. The Theory of the Leisure Class. Oxford: Oxford University Press.) stresses a particular type of institution as extremely important in the inculcation of the concepts of goods, namely, the leisure class, which is an upper socioeconomic class, particularly in material terms. As highlighted by Veblen (1899Veblen, T. (2007) [1899]. The Theory of the Leisure Class. Oxford: Oxford University Press.), leisure classes are by custom exempt or excluded from practicing industrial occupations. Members of the leisure class are employed in tasks associated with a degree of honor. Status is an intrinsic part of the leisure class. Not only tasks but also situations and goods that are characteristic of the leisure class become powerful signs of status. According to Dewey (1934Dewey, J. (1934). Art as experience. In S. Haack, & R. Lane (2006). Pragmatism, old & new (pp. 423-441). New York: Prometheus Books.), status relies on a “long history of unquestionable admiration,” which is implied in institutionalized concepts. A good that achieves status signifies that this good reflects an esthetic that has been established socially and evolutionarily (see Dewey, 1934Dewey, J. (1934). Art as experience. In S. Haack, & R. Lane (2006). Pragmatism, old & new (pp. 423-441). New York: Prometheus Books.).

As stressed by Veblen (1899Veblen, T. (2007) [1899]. The Theory of the Leisure Class. Oxford: Oxford University Press.), the leisure class can be found in its best development in modern societies because, in these societies, distinctions between classes and the classification of groups are clearly observed as a result of employment differences. Dewey (1921Dewey, J. (1921). Human nature and conduct: an introduction to social psychology. New York: DC Heath & Co Publishers .) reinforces Veblen’s argument by affirming that it is possible to find the influence of social factors in creating personal characters in everyday life. One of these factors, Dewey stresses, is the habit of making social classifications, such as features attributed to the rich and poor and membership to a specific group. For Veblen (1899Veblen, T. (2007) [1899]. The Theory of the Leisure Class. Oxford: Oxford University Press.), the evolution of culture generates a leisure class and a related social classification at approximately the same time as the beginning of the private ownership of goods. The private ownership of goods is the result of conventional beliefs perpetuated within the social structure. The central point is that the leisure class and ownership of goods emerge simultaneously. Both arise from the desire of successful people to exhibit their prowess. Hence, the ownership of goods is not simply about property or personal consumption; it is also about convention and demonstrating the use of these goods. Consistent with this idea, the property system is installed gradually (Veblen, 1899Veblen, T. (2007) [1899]. The Theory of the Leisure Class. Oxford: Oxford University Press.). In Veblen’s social theory, it is the biased tradition of private ownership that inculcates notions of honor and status based on goods.

According to Veblen (1899Veblen, T. (2007) [1899]. The Theory of the Leisure Class. Oxford: Oxford University Press.), wherever there is private property, people are distinguished by the possession of goods, which is an efficient way to express wealth socially. Veblen (1899Veblen, T. (2007) [1899]. The Theory of the Leisure Class. Oxford: Oxford University Press.) stresses that in a society in which almost all goods are private property, the necessity for members of the poorer class to earn their livelihoods is a powerful and constant incentive. As soon as their subsistence is guaranteed, emulation becomes a key guideline for their behavior (Veblen, 1899Veblen, T. (2007) [1899]. The Theory of the Leisure Class. Oxford: Oxford University Press.). Consequently, the existence of the leisure class, in Veblen’s theory, pertains less to collective classification and more to social selection. This social selection occurs based on one’s capacity to emulate the way of life of the leisure class. Dewey (1939bDewey, J. (1939b). Culture and human nature. In J. McDermott (1981). The Philosophy of John Dewey (pp. 679-696). Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press .) reinforces this point by stressing that there is satisfaction stemming from the sense of union with others. This satisfaction comes from what is communicated to others. The reward of this satisfaction is associated with an institutionalized sense of social fulfillment (Dewey, 1930Dewey, J. (1930). The lost individual. In J. McDermott (1981). The Philosophy of John Dewey (pp. 598-608). Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press .).

For Veblen (1899Veblen, T. (2007) [1899]. The Theory of the Leisure Class. Oxford: Oxford University Press.), this social fulfillment relies on the consumption of goods because of their status, which, in turn, is guided by the emulation of the leisure class. Dewey (1910aDewey, J. (1910a). How we think, New York: DC Heath & Co Publishers.) emphasizes this point by stressing that social status, which is associated with the position that people think they occupy in a society, plays a key role in their decisions. Goods regarded as objects acquired by the leisure class become a strong signal of success. Consequently, in Veblen’s view (1899), social selection occurs based on people’s capacity to emulate behavior based on the way of life of the leisure class. According to this logic, Veblen’s conspicuous consumer seeks to consume like the higher social class wherever possible.

By emphasizing a social emulative logic of consumption mediated by the leisure class, Veblen’s approach regarding consumption relies strictly on its feature of conspicuousness. Conspicuous consumption can be understood as wasteful monetary expenditure motivated by social esteem. According to Trigg (2001Trigg, A. (2001). Veblen, Bourdieu, and conspicuous consumption. Journal of Economic Issues , 35(1), 99-115.), Veblen’s conspicuous consumption means spending money on goods to display wealth to other members of society. Shipman (2004Shipman, A. (2004). Lauding the leisure class: symbolic content and conspicuous consumption. Review of Social Economy, 62(3), 277-289.) emphasizes that the central aspect of Veblen’s conspicuous consumption is the connection of goods to the impulse to “waste” despite exhibiting “taste.” The impulse to waste can be understood as a taste that involves social learning through the institution of the leisure class (Ramstad, 1998Ramstad, Y. (1998). Veblen’s propensity to emulation: is it passé? In D. Brown, (1998). Thorstein Veblen in the twenty-first century . Cheltenham: Edward Elgar .). The conspicuous consumer buys goods for the status they represent, based on wastefulness, and, thus, pays for particular features of these products. By this logic, there exists an understanding of how one can seek status, which can be expressed in concrete, objective ways: emulating the behavior of the leisure class by buying the goods its members buy (Veblen, 1899Veblen, T. (2007) [1899]. The Theory of the Leisure Class. Oxford: Oxford University Press.).

According to this logic, satisfaction is institutionally established and inculcated in consumers’ decision-making through habits. By emulation, consumers learn which goods should be included in their decision-making and how to acquire them. According to Veblen’s theory, in societies in which subsistence is guaranteed, there is a tendency for consumption to be a result, not so much of physical demands, but social demands. Thus, satisfaction and its absence are not physical outcomes. Dissatisfaction is a mental phenomenon; it is the result of failing to follow emulative logic, and in this case, the consumer can understand the institutionally evolved concepts of goods but cannot satisfy her/his impulse with the relevant goods (for example, because of a lack of financial resources). Through her/his capacity to put habits in practice, the conspicuous consumer shows her/his power, which is a social power.

5. FINAL COMMENTS

Veblen’s understanding of conspicuous consumption relies on the significance of habits and institutions in consumer decision-making. Veblen’s approach has offered an innovative alternative for understanding human behavior, replacing the marginalist rational calculator with a biological, cultural, and historical being. Moreover, Veblen’s perspective was related to his pragmatist philosophical references. Given this background, our study addressed selected elements of Veblen’s philosophical background to revisit his understanding of conspicuous consumption. Our starting subject was the process through which a conspicuous consumer perceives a habit. This analysis guided our discussion of the Veblenian notion of instinct with the assistance of William James’s concept of appropriation. Veblen’s understanding of the conspicuous consumer considered appropriation-the connection between an inner impulse to consume and a good-as a part of instinct. Conversely, the appropriation process is not an individual one; it is necessarily social.

According to Peirce’s perspective on social impulse, by observing others, a conspicuous consumer can associate beliefs or doubts with the behavior of others. The result of a belief is the satisfaction of being free from the pressure to consume, whereas the result of a doubt is irritation at continuing to experience such pressure. Hence, consumers tend to establish beliefs by observing others. A conspicuous consumer can replace, review, or reinforce her/his beliefs. A reinforcement of one’s beliefs culminates in habits that inhibit and change one’s inner impulses to consume. As they are based on observation, habits are social phenomena that rely on generalized behavioral results.

Such habits occur within a community, and its institutions are outgrowths of those habits. Veblen stressed a key institution that is responsible for social classification and selection of people, namely, the leisure class-the higher social class in material terms. Consumption similar to that of the leisure class confers status and achievement of social esteem. The result is that satisfaction from consumption is a social product instead of the satisfaction of an inner impulse to consume. In this approach, Dewey’s notion of socialization and the inculcation of concepts by habits play a key role. Despite relying on some pragmatist thinkers’ relevant ideas in an attempt to reassess a key subject of Veblen’s theory-namely, his conspicuous consumer concept-this study does not exhaust all possible connections between Veblen’s social theory and pragmatism on this subject. We understand that pragmatist philosophy offers a rich theoretical and methodological reference to the researcher concerned with the nature and role of institutions and institutional dynamics. Pragmatism is historically and philosophically connected to Original Institutionalism, especially when used as a reference to the pioneer ideas of Thorstein Veblen.

REFERENCES

  • Almeida, F. (2014). Thorstein Veblen and Albert Bandura: a modern psychological reading of the conspicuous consumer. Journal of Economic Issues, 48(1), 109-122.
  • Apel, Karl (1967). Charles S. Peirce: From Pragmatism to Pragmaticism. Amhrest: University of Massachusetts Press.
  • Argyrous, G., & Sethi, R. (1996). The theory of evolution and the evolution of theory: Veblen’s methodology in contemporary perspective. Cambridge Journal of Economics, 20, 475-495.
  • Bain, A. (1859). The Emotions and the Will. New York. D. Appleton & Company.
  • Brown, D. (1998). Thorstein Veblen in the twenty-first century, Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
  • Camic, C. (2012). Schooling for Heterodoxy: On the Foundations of Thorstein Veblen’s Institutional Economics. In: Reinert, E and Viano, F. (2012). Thorstein Veblen: Economics for an Age of Crisis. London: Anthem Press.
  • Cordes, C. (2005). Veblen’s “Instinct of Workmanship,” its cognitive foundations, and some implications for economic theory. Journal of Economic Issues , 39(1), 1-20.
  • Darwin, C. (1872). The expression of the emotions in man and animals. London: John Murray.
  • Dewey, J. (1910a). How we think, New York: DC Heath & Co Publishers.
  • Dewey, J. (1910b). The experimental theory of knowledge. In J. McDermott (1981). The Philosophy of John Dewey (pp. 175-193). Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press.
  • Dewey, J. (1921). Human nature and conduct: an introduction to social psychology. New York: DC Heath & Co Publishers .
  • Dewey, J. (1930). The lost individual. In J. McDermott (1981). The Philosophy of John Dewey (pp. 598-608). Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press .
  • Dewey, J. (1931). The practical character of reality. In J. McDermott (1981). The Philosophy of John Dewey (pp. 207-222). Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press .
  • Dewey, J. (1934). Art as experience. In S. Haack, & R. Lane (2006). Pragmatism, old & new (pp. 423-441). New York: Prometheus Books.
  • Dewey, J. (1939a). Having an experience. In J. McDermott (1981). The Philosophy of John Dewey (pp. 554-573). Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press .
  • Dewey, J. (1939b). Culture and human nature. In J. McDermott (1981). The Philosophy of John Dewey (pp. 679-696). Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press .
  • Dyer, A. (1986). Veblen on scientific creativity: the influence of Charles S. Peirce. Journal of Economic Issues , 20(1), 21-41.
  • Edgell, S., & Tilman, R. (1989). The intellectual antecedents of Thorstein Veblen: a reappraisal. Journal of Economic Issues , 23(4), 1003-1026.
  • Fitzgerald, J. (1968). Peirce’s Theory of Inquiry. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society. 4(3), 130-143.
  • Griffin, R. (1998). What Veblen owed to Peirce-the social theory of logic. Journal of Economic Issues , 32(3), 733-757.
  • Haack, S., & Lane, R. (2006). Pragmatism, old & new . New York: Prometheus Books .
  • Hall, J., & Whybrow, O. (2008) “Continuity and Continuousness: The Chain of Ideas Linking Peirce’s Synechism to Veblen’s Cumulative Causation.” Journal of Economic Issues , 42 (2), 349-355.
  • Hamilton, W. (1919). The institutional approach to economic theory. American Economic Review, 9(1), 309-318.
  • Hodgson, G. (1998a). The approach of institutional economics. Journal of Economic Literature, 36, 166-192.
  • Hodgson, G. (1998b). On the Evolution of Thorstein Veblen’s Evolutionary Economics. Cambridge Journal of Economics , 22(4), 15-431
  • Hodgson, G. (2002). The evolution of institutions: an agenda for future theoretical research. Constitutional Political Economy, 13(2), 111-127.
  • Hodgson, G. (2004a) The evolution of institutional economics: agency, structure and Darwinism in American institutionalism. London: Routledge.
  • Hodgson, G. (2004b). Reclaiming habit for institutional economics. Journal of Economic Psychology, 25: 651-660.
  • James, W. (1904). Does ‘Consciousness’ Exist? The Journal of Philosophy Psychology and Scientific Methods. 1(18), 477-491.
  • James, W. (1905). How Two Minds Can Know One Thing. The Journal of Philosophy Psychology and Scientific Methods . 2(7), 176-181.
  • James, W. (2007) [originally published 1890a]. The principles of psychology: volume 1. New York: Cosimo.
  • James, W. (2007) [originally published in 1890b]. The principles of psychology: volume 2. New York: Cosimo .
  • James, W. (2006) [originally published in 1906]. Pragmatism’s Conception of Truth. In S. Haack, & R. Lane. Pragmatism, old & new (pp. 309-329). New York: Prometheus Books .
  • Jennings, A. & Waller. W. (1998). The Place of Biological Science in Veblen’s Economics. History of Political Economy, 30 (2), 189-217.
  • Latsis, J. (2009). Veblen on the machine process and technological change. Cambridge Journal of Economics , 34, 601-615.
  • Liebhafsky, E. (1993). The influence of Charles Sanders Peirce on Institutional Economics. Journal of Economic Issues , 27(3), 741-754.
  • Margolis, J. (1998). Peirce’s Fallibilism. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society , 34(3), 535-569.
  • McDermott, J. (1981). The Philosophy of John Dewey . Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press .
  • Mirowski, P. (1987). The philosophical bases of institutional economics. Journal of Economic Issues , 21(3), 1001-1038.
  • Peirce, C. (1868). Some consequences of four incapacities. In S. Haack, & R. Lane. (2006). Pragmatism, old & new (pp. 69-105). New York: Prometheus Books .
  • Peirce, C. (1877). The fixation of belief. In S. Haack, & R. Lane. (2006). Pragmatism, old & new (pp. 107-126). New York: Prometheus Books .
  • Peirce, C. (1878). How to make our ideas clear. In S. Haack, & R. Lane. (2006). Pragmatism, old & new (pp. 127-150). New York: Prometheus Books .
  • Peirce, C. (1892). Lessons from the history of scientific thought. In P. Wiener. (1966). Charles S. Peirce: selected writings (pp. 227-321). New York: Dover Publications.
  • Peirce, C. (1905). What Pragmatism is? The Monist, 15 (2), 161-181.
  • Peirce, C. (1994). The Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. Edited by Charles Hartshone, Paul Weiss and Arthur Burks. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Ramstad, Y. (1998). Veblen’s propensity to emulation: is it passé? In D. Brown, (1998). Thorstein Veblen in the twenty-first century . Cheltenham: Edward Elgar .
  • Rutherford, M. (2011). The institutionalist movement in American economics, 1918-1947: science and social control. Cambridge: the Cambridge University Press.
  • Shipman, A. (2004). Lauding the leisure class: symbolic content and conspicuous consumption. Review of Social Economy, 62(3), 277-289.
  • Tilman, R. (2007). Thorstein Veblen and the Enrichment of Evolutionary Naturalism. London: University of Missouri Press.
  • Trigg, A. (2001). Veblen, Bourdieu, and conspicuous consumption. Journal of Economic Issues , 35(1), 99-115.
  • Twomey, P. (1998). Reviving Veblenian economic psychology. Cambridge Journal of Economics , 22, 433-448.
  • Veblen, T. (1884). Kant’s Critique of Judgment. Journal of Speculative Philosophy 18(3): 260-274
  • Veblen, T. (1998). Why is economics not an evolutionary science? Cambridge Journal of Economics , 22, 403-414. [Originally published in 1898 in The Quarterly Journal of Economics, July, 373-397].
  • Veblen, T. (2007) [1899]. The Theory of the Leisure Class. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Veblen, T. (1900). The Preconceptions of Economic Science III. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 14 (5), 240-269,
  • Veblen, T. (1906). The place of science in the modern civilization. The American Journal of Sociology, 11(5), 585-609.
  • Veblen, T. (1909). The limitations of marginal utility. Journal of Political Economy, 17(9), 620-636.
  • Veblen, T. (2006). [1914]. The instinct of workmanship and the state of the industrial arts. New York: Cosimo .
  • Veblen, T. (2005) [1919]. The vested interests and the common man. New York: Cosimo .
  • Veblen, T. (1925). Economic theory in the calculable future. American Economic Review , 15(1), 48-55.
  • Wiener, P. (1966). Charles S. Peirce: selected writings . New York: Dover Publications .
  • wright, C. (1873). Evolution of Self-Consciousness. In: Norton, C. (1877). Philosophical discussions by Chauncey Wright. New York: Lennox Hill.
  • 1
    We must remember that Veblen (1900Veblen, T. (1900). The Preconceptions of Economic Science III. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 14 (5), 240-269,) coined the word “neoclassical” mainly to refer to the ideas spread by the Marginalist Revolution.
  • 2
    Peirce was a temporary lecturer at John Hopkins University from 1879 to 1884 (Liebhafsky, 1993Liebhafsky, E. (1993). The influence of Charles Sanders Peirce on Institutional Economics. Journal of Economic Issues , 27(3), 741-754.).
  • 3
    From his 1905 paper, “What Pragmatism is?”, Peirce began to call his philosophical perspective as “pragmaticism.” This was a reaction to the bad use of the term “pragmatism,” as Peirce (1905Peirce, C. (1905). What Pragmatism is? The Monist, 15 (2), 161-181., p. 165) states: “at present, the word begins to be met with occasionally in the literary journals, where it gets abused in the merciless way that words have to expect when they fall into literary clutches [...] So then, the writer, finding his bantling ‘pragmatism’ so promoted, feels that it is time to kiss his child good-by and relinquish it to its higher destiny; while to serve the precise purpose of expressing the original definition, he begs to announce the birth of the word ‘pragmaticism,’ which is ugly enough to be safe from kidnappers.”
  • 4
    Veblen (1884Veblen, T. (1884). Kant’s Critique of Judgment. Journal of Speculative Philosophy 18(3): 260-274) is essential for one to perceive Peirce’s influence on Veblen’s writings as it describes precisely Peirce’s three fundamental principles of logic: (i) the supremacy of inductive reasoning, (ii) the mediating role of human apprehension, and (iii) the power of judgment of the human mind. These principles, through which Veblen describes Kant’s work, constitute evidence toward the affinity between Peirce and Kant regarding the elaboration of scientific hypotheses. The idea that such hypotheses are the result of the mediating role of the human mind must be highlighted here as a starting point to trace the connections between Veblen’s understanding of scientific inquiry and Peirce’s conception of human logic.
  • 5
    For example, to acquire the habit of a healthy life suggests denying several types of behaviors, such as smoking, eating greasy food, and drinking beer on a daily basis. However, the habit of a healthy life also suggests participating in sports, eating fruit and vegetables, and drinking water regularly as desirable types of behavior. The habit of a healthy life as described here offers an illustration of behaviors that can and cannot imply a habit. This example does not illustrate Veblenian habits in a general sense, because not necessarily being implied by a behavior is only one feature of Veblenian habits. Later on, we consider the other features of habits according to Veblen.
  • 6
    This sentence may suggest that the only source of satisfaction for a consumer is the end of her/his inner impulses’ pressure to consume but this is quite wrong from Veblen’s perspective. According to Veblen (1899Veblen, T. (2007) [1899]. The Theory of the Leisure Class. Oxford: Oxford University Press.), institutional pressures are important pressures a consumer must attend to so as to be satisfied. This issue is introduced later in this section and further emphasized in subsequent sections. In addition, since this study references satisfaction as a result of an inner impulse, it is important to highlight that Veblen rejects the utilitarian pleasure-pain decision-making logic (Argyrous and Sethi, 1996Argyrous, G., & Sethi, R. (1996). The theory of evolution and the evolution of theory: Veblen’s methodology in contemporary perspective. Cambridge Journal of Economics, 20, 475-495.; Veblen, 1898Veblen, T. (1998). Why is economics not an evolutionary science? Cambridge Journal of Economics , 22, 403-414. [Originally published in 1898 in The Quarterly Journal of Economics, July, 373-397]., 1909Veblen, T. (1909). The limitations of marginal utility. Journal of Political Economy, 17(9), 620-636.). The passage below is usually quoted in the context of strong disapproval of the traditional economics-based approach to decision-making: “The hedonistic conception of man is that of a lightning calculator of pleasures and pains, who oscillates like a homogeneous globule of desire of happiness under the impulse of stimuli that shift him about the area but leave him intact. He has neither antecedent nor consequent. He is an isolated, definitive human datum, in stable equilibrium except for the buffets of the impinging forces that displace him in one direction or another … The later psychology, re-enforced by modern anthropological research, gives a different conception of human nature. According to this conception, it is the characteristic of man to do something, not simply to suffer pleasures and pains through the impact of suitable forces. He is not simply a bundle of desires that are to be saturated by being placed in the path of the forces of the environment, but rather a coherent structure of propensities and habits which seeks realization and expression in an unfolding activity” (Veblen, 1898Veblen, T. (1998). Why is economics not an evolutionary science? Cambridge Journal of Economics , 22, 403-414. [Originally published in 1898 in The Quarterly Journal of Economics, July, 373-397]., pp. 389-390).Veblen believed that an individualistic pleasure-pain reading of human behavior is not enough. From a Veblenian perspective, the socialization process adds other layers to decision-making. This study further clarifies this point.
  • 7
    James (1890bJames, W. (2007) [originally published in 1890b]. The principles of psychology: volume 2. New York: Cosimo .) emphasizes that human beings’ motivation to behave in a certain way is like that of any other creature, and human beings’ inner impulses are as “blind” as those of other creatures.
  • 8
    For Dewey (1921Dewey, J. (1921). Human nature and conduct: an introduction to social psychology. New York: DC Heath & Co Publishers .), repetition is not even the essence of habit. However, repetition can be an incident of many habits. An individual looking for a healthier life provides an example of a habit that is not associated with repetition. Foregoing sugar, fatty food, and smoking can be habits acquired by the individual. These habits do not imply repetitive behavior. For Dewey (1921Dewey, J. (1921). Human nature and conduct: an introduction to social psychology. New York: DC Heath & Co Publishers .), the essence of a habit is a predisposition to ways or modes of behavior. A habit means special sensitivity or accessibility to certain classes of stimuli.
  • 9
    Veblen stresses some types of instinct. The main types are the instinct of workmanship, parental bent, and idle curiosity. However, given the goal of this study, Veblen’s specific types of instinct are not central to the analysis. The central issue is Veblen’s perspective on instincts and the manner in which they can influence consumer decision-making. For more information about the instinct of workmanship, parental bent, and idle curiosity, see Latsis (2009Latsis, J. (2009). Veblen on the machine process and technological change. Cambridge Journal of Economics , 34, 601-615.).
  • 10
    Apel (1967Apel, Karl (1967). Charles S. Peirce: From Pragmatism to Pragmaticism. Amhrest: University of Massachusetts Press. , p. 54) indicates that Peirce (1877Peirce, C. (1877). The fixation of belief. In S. Haack, & R. Lane. (2006). Pragmatism, old & new (pp. 107-126). New York: Prometheus Books ., 1878Peirce, C. (1878). How to make our ideas clear. In S. Haack, & R. Lane. (2006). Pragmatism, old & new (pp. 127-150). New York: Prometheus Books .) expressed the ideas of Peirce’s earlier works: “Peirce had in fact already rather distinctly formulated the point that he later, for clarification, termed the ‘pragmatic maxim,’ before the discussions in the Metaphysical Club (winter 1871 to winter 1872). He did this, for example, in a passage in the 1869 essay, but the point was particularly unmistakable in the Berkeley review of 1871.”
  • 11
    Our reference to Peirce’s ideas reflects this complicated relation with James and Dewey’s perspective. From a complementary viewpoint, our main references are exactly the foundational writings of the pragmatist school, that is, Peirce (1877Peirce, C. (1877). The fixation of belief. In S. Haack, & R. Lane. (2006). Pragmatism, old & new (pp. 107-126). New York: Prometheus Books .) and Peirce (1878Peirce, C. (1878). How to make our ideas clear. In S. Haack, & R. Lane. (2006). Pragmatism, old & new (pp. 127-150). New York: Prometheus Books .). Subsequently, we will restrict our analysis to the ideas of the “young Peirce.”
  • 12
    The Metaphysical Club was a conversational group from 1871 to 1872, formed in Cambridge, Massachusetts, by Oliver Wendell Holmes Jr., William James, Charles Sanders Peirce, Chauncey Wright, John Fiske, Francis Ellingwood Abbot, Nicholas St. John Green, and Joseph Bangs Warner.
  • 13
    It is important to note that Peirce’s perspective is rooted in Chauncey Wright’s philosophy, which combined positivist ideas with evolutionary Darwinism. In “Evolution of Self-Consciousness” (1873wright, C. (1873). Evolution of Self-Consciousness. In: Norton, C. (1877). Philosophical discussions by Chauncey Wright. New York: Lennox Hill.), Wright established a continuity line between animal instincts and human intelligence based on the role of adaptive behavior throughout history (see also Apel, 1967Apel, Karl (1967). Charles S. Peirce: From Pragmatism to Pragmaticism. Amhrest: University of Massachusetts Press. , pp. 56-57).
  • 14
    It is important to indicate that the belief-doubt theory establishes the behavioral support of Peirce’s evolutionary philosophy. Peirce (1877Peirce, C. (1877). The fixation of belief. In S. Haack, & R. Lane. (2006). Pragmatism, old & new (pp. 107-126). New York: Prometheus Books .) presents and criticizes three different methods that the human mind appeals to for fixing a belief. The first method is called “the method of tenacity” and refers to how the human mind is inclined to keep the beliefs it already has established, or defend these beliefs as a “steady and immovable faith,” and reject whatever beliefs it has already rejected. The second method is called “the method of authority” and refers to the moment when organizations and their institutions establish beliefs in human minds, as has happened in several moments in human history: “[t]his method has, from the earliest times, been more of the chief means of upholding correct theological and political doctrines, and of preserving their universal or catholic character […] Wherever there is an aristocracy, or a guild, or any association of a class of men whose interests depend, or are supposed to depend, on certain propositions, there will be inevitably some traces of this natural product of social feeling.” The third method is the Cartesian “a priori method,” where beliefs become firm because the propositions in question are guaranteed by the light of reason (implanted by God in our minds), which is independent of individual perspective or the institutional environment. For Peirce (1877Peirce, C. (1877). The fixation of belief. In S. Haack, & R. Lane. (2006). Pragmatism, old & new (pp. 107-126). New York: Prometheus Books .), these three methods for forming a belief all have the same problem: they ignore an important evolutionary trace in human nature, “social impulse.”
  • 15
    This behavioral disposition is the main support for Peirce’s “fallibilist” understanding of the logic of science. For more information, we refer the reader to Margolis (1998Margolis, J. (1998). Peirce’s Fallibilism. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society , 34(3), 535-569.).
  • 16
    Returning to our example of healthy life habits, a consumer may identify a bodybuilder as someone whose behavior should be classified as healthy. Hence, the bodybuilder is identified as a model of behavior and a belief is established. On the other hand, a consumer looking to establish healthy habits may view bodybuilders as athletes. Therefore, a bodybuilder would not be a model of behavior because the consumer does not desire to be an athlete but simply wants to be healthy. Consequently, doubts occur through non-identification with a model of behavior.
  • 17
    Let us suppose that a consumer identifies a bodybuilder as a model of behavior associated with healthy habits. Hence, the consumer builds beliefs that rely on impulse-good connections, such as a carbohydrate-rich diet. However, when the consumer starts such a diet, she/he may perceive that it is not as healthy as she/he believed. Consequently, the belief becomes a doubt.
  • 18
    In our example, the consumer continues to search for behaviors associated with healthy habits but becomes irritated by the failure to find such behaviors.
  • 19
    Dewey (1910aDewey, J. (1910a). How we think, New York: DC Heath & Co Publishers.) introduces consumers’ thoughts into this logic. For Dewey (1910aDewey, J. (1910a). How we think, New York: DC Heath & Co Publishers.), thought is usually associated with beliefs, which rely on some evidence or testimony. Thoughts constitute beliefs that rely on some basis, usually an observational one (Dewey, 1910aDewey, J. (1910a). How we think, New York: DC Heath & Co Publishers.). A thought can be a supposition that can establish a belief, transform a belief into a doubt, or reinforce a belief. According to Peirce (1878Peirce, C. (1878). How to make our ideas clear. In S. Haack, & R. Lane. (2006). Pragmatism, old & new (pp. 127-150). New York: Prometheus Books ., p. 132), “[…] the production of belief is the sole function of thought.” According to Peirce (1892Peirce, C. (1892). Lessons from the history of scientific thought. In P. Wiener. (1966). Charles S. Peirce: selected writings (pp. 227-321). New York: Dover Publications.), there are three sources of one’s developing thoughts: (1) the formation of habits based on beliefs, (2) the abandonment up of habits due to doubts, and (3) the combination of different beliefs resulting in a new variation. The combination of different beliefs develop according to Darwinian evolution (Peirce, 1892Peirce, C. (1892). Lessons from the history of scientific thought. In P. Wiener. (1966). Charles S. Peirce: selected writings (pp. 227-321). New York: Dover Publications., p. 257). The combination of (1) and (2) implies that beliefs are changed by doubts. When a belief is questionable, there is a struggle between the belief and the doubt about it. James (1906James, W. (2006) [originally published in 1906]. Pragmatism’s Conception of Truth. In S. Haack, & R. Lane. Pragmatism, old & new (pp. 309-329). New York: Prometheus Books .) reinforces this point by highlighting that consumers’ experiences offer ways to build a behavioral process that generates the possibility for substituting a belief.
  • 20
    See Hodgson (1998bHodgson, G. (1998b). On the Evolution of Thorstein Veblen’s Evolutionary Economics. Cambridge Journal of Economics , 22(4), 15-431) and Hodgson (2004bHodgson, G. (2004b). Reclaiming habit for institutional economics. Journal of Economic Psychology, 25: 651-660. ) for an alternative perspective.
  • *
    Note: A previous version of this paper was presented at the 46th ANPEC meeting, Rio de Janeiro, December 2018. The authors thank the participants in this event. This research has been supported by the Conselho Nacional de Desenvolvimento Científico e Tecnológico (CNPq).
  • 21
    JEL Classification: B15; B52.

Publication Dates

  • Publication in this collection
    20 Feb 2023
  • Date of issue
    Jan-Mar 2023

History

  • Received
    22 Apr 2021
  • Accepted
    16 Dec 2021
Centro de Economia Política Rua Araripina, 106, CEP 05603-030 São Paulo - SP, Tel. (55 11) 3816-6053 - São Paulo - SP - Brazil
E-mail: cecilia.heise@bjpe.org.br