Acessibilidade / Reportar erro

On the metaphysical role of historicity

O papel metafísico da historicidade

ABSTRACT

I argue that the philosophy of historicity forms the metaphysical core of the historical way of thinking and, therefore, is relevant as a philosophy of history and historiography. From this perspective, the scope of the theorization of history should extend to the substantive metaphysical ground in which the modern idea of history was built to disclose the main temporal character of the historical phenomena to which historicity refers. Hence, since my goal here is the clarification of the meaningfulness of historicity, I examine the philosophical tradition that investigates the transient nature of reality-a key feature of the historicity of existence represented by G. W. F. Hegel, F. W. J. Schelling, and, above all, Martin Heidegger-since this tradition includes especially valuable ontological arguments for illuminating hidden presuppositions in the still-relevant understanding of history.

Keywords:
historicity; temporality; metaphysics

RESUMO

Proponho que uma filosofia da historicidade é o cerne metafísico do modo histórico de pensar, logo, tão relevante quanto uma filosofia da história e da historiografia. Para o estudo do significado do caráter temporal dos fenômenos históricos, quer dizer, para o exame da historicidade, a teorização sobre a história deve ampliar seu escopo de investigação até o fundamento metafísico substantivo sob o qual a ideia moderna de história foi construída. Assim, na medida que a explicação do sentido da historicidade é o objetivo deste artigo, a tradição filosófica que investiga a essência da natureza transitória da realidade, representada principalmente por G. W. F. Hegel, F. W. J. Schelling e, sobretudo, Martin Heidegger, será examinada, dado que ela possui argumentos ontológicos valiosos para iluminar alguns pressupostos ocultos presentes no que compreendemos sobre o que é a história.

Palavras-chave:
historicidade; temporalidade; metafísica

Amid the revision and even rejection of many theoretical propositions regarding historicism, questions about the elementary temporal nature of history continue to play a central role in historical thinking. Reinhart Koselleck, for instance, argued that historical time is one of the most important concepts for understanding the social design of the experience of time from the historical perspective and the core of contemporary discussions of the multiple temporalities in history (JORDHEIM, 2012JORDHEIM, Helge. Against Periodization: Koselleck’s Theory of Multiple Temporalities. History and Theory, v. 51, n. 2, p. 151-171, 2012.; MUDROVCIC, 2014MUDROVCIC, María Inés. Time, History, and Philosophy of History. Journal of the Philosophy of History, v. 8, n. 2, p. 217-242, 2014.). The significance of the “simultaneity of the nonsimultaneous” (LANDWEHR, 2012LANDWEHR, Achim. Von der, Gleichzeitigkeit des Ungleichzeitigen’. Historische Zeitschrift, v. 295, n. 1, p. 1-34, 2012.), the diagnosis of the contemporary socio-political uses of time (TURIN, 2019TURIN, Rodrigo. Tempos precários: aceleração, historicidade e semântica neoliberal. Dansk: Zazie Edições, 2019.), and the concerns about the Anthropocene (CHAKRABARTY, 2017CHAKRABARTY, Dipesh. The Future of the Human Sciences in the Age of Humans: A Note. European Journal of Social Theory, v. 20, n. 1, p. 39-43, 2017.) are among the discussions that have built on Koselleck’s analysis of the meanings of historical time, which serve to demonstrate the power of this metahistorical category and the problematic nature of time for historians.

Nevertheless, as relevant and useful as these questions may be, other aspects of the temporal nature of history can be objects of inquiry. The present study draws attention to one of these aspects, the metaphysical ground that history still occupies as a phenomenon and knowledge. In other words, I propose taking a step back from Koselleck’s anthropological notion of historical time to clarify or, in some cases, question the very idea of time, which is sometimes taken for granted.

This query emerges from a philosophical approach to history involving the endeavor to arrive at a fundamental understanding of “the historical” that distinguishes history from historiography-the ancient distinction between res gestae and historia rerum gestarum-as well as from historicity, which is a 19th century conceptual novelty (Cf. KOSLOWSKI, 2005KOSLOWSKI, Peter. The Discovery of Historicity in German Idealism and Historism. Berlin, Heidelberg, New York: Springer, 2005.). In this context, historicity represents the introduction of the ontological gaze into “the historical”. Thus, while historiography would be the epistemologically justified and ethically based intellectual elaboration of history, assumed to be constructed on concrete experience, historicity refers to the abstract ontological feature derived from a temporal aspect that enables the historical experience (Cf. LYOTARD, 1954LYOTARD, J-F. La Phénoménologie. Paris: PUF, 1954.). Philosophy then emphasizes the notion of historicity as an elementary metaphysical principle based on the ontological understanding of the nature of history as, fundamentally, a logical problem regarding the ambivalent becoming and perseverance of existence, that is, an expression of the idea of time (Cf. ANKERSMIT, 2012ANKERSMIT, Frank. 2012. Meaning, Truth and Reference in Historical Representation. New York: Cornell University Press, 2012., p. 29).1 1 See Augusto de Carvalho. A lógica do tempo e de outras palavras fundamentais. Trans/Form/Ação 43/3, 2020. (p. 187-192)

Historians should acknowledge that any question about time is entangled in a basic metaphysical puzzle since the well-known inconsistency derived from the being of time2 2 See, for instance, McTaggart’s arguments (1908). , and the temporality of existence is the root of all metaphysics. In fact, metaphysics depends on clarification of the meanings of time, and time is the main question in any and all metaphysical considerations (Cf. WHITEHEAD, 1978WHITEHEAD, A. N. Process and Reality. New York: The Free Press, 1978., p. 208-209; KUKI, 2012KUKI, Shūzō. Gūzensei no Mondai. [The question of contingency]. Tokyo: Iwanami Bunko, 2012., p. 13-14; SILVA, 2019SILVA, Diogo C. P. Kuki Shūzō’s Redefinition of Metaphysics Through Contingency. International Journal of the Philosophical Association of Japan, v. 3, p. 190-206, 2019.). In the words of SolomyakSOLOMYAK, Olla. Temporal Ontology and the Metaphysics of Perspectives. Erkenntnis, v. 85, p. 431-453, 2018., “questions surrounding the metaphysics of time seem to be as substantive as metaphysical issues get-it would be difficult to dismiss issues concerning the nature of time as meaningless without dismissing metaphysics as a whole” (2018, p. 431).

The basic phenomenon of time, its transience, and its paradoxical nature, as an affirmation and subsequent negation of being-being that always becomes non-being-hence turns out to be the (il)logical core of the ontological design of history (BAUER, 1963BAUER, Gerhard. Geschichtlichkeit: Wege und Irrwege eines Begriffs. [Historicity: ways and wanderings of a concept]. Berlin: de Gruyter, 1963., p. 119; VON RENTHE-FINK, 1974VON RENTHE-FINK, Leonhard. “Geschichtlichkeit [Historicity].” In: RITTER, Joachim et al. (ed.). Historisches Wörterbuch der Philosophie [3]. Basel: Schwabe, 1974. p. 404-408. , p. 407; DE CARVALHO, 2022DE CARVALHO, Augusto. A Brief History of Historicity. O que nos faz pensar, v. 30, n. 50, p. 196-221, 2022. ). In short, this temporal (non)sense is an enigma on which philosophers such as Martin Heidegger, F. W. J. Schelling, and G. W. F. Hegel worked carefully to codify a philosophy of historicity. Their findings show that “ontological inquiries belong to the philosophy of history no less than epistemological investigations” (SCHOLZ, 2014SCHOLZ, Oliver. Philosophy of History: Metaphysics and Epistemology. In: KAISER, M. I. et al. (ed.). Explanation in the Special Sciences: The Case of Biology and History (Synthese Library). Dordrecht: Springer, 2014. p. 245-253., p. 247) by demonstrating the reasons why and the ways in which metaphysical assumptions about the role of time in reality are unavoidable.3 3 In a way, this essay responds to Bevernage (2012) proposition, but from a speculative or philosophical standpoint.

Based on this philosophical survey of the metaphysical territory of history, I demonstrate the extent to which historical, concrete reality can be understood or theoretically justified by means of an investigation into what is disclosed as the historicity of existence-not the supposed context of an entity, event, or phenomenon but its very temporal nature. Therefore, I investigate philosophies of historicity by conducting a metaphysical analysis of the historical character of existence in general. This step back regarding the so-called “substantive” philosophies of history, then, involves the rediscovery of questions that remain central to historical thought despite their neglect in critical4 4 It is worthy to note that R. G. Collingwood was one of the firsts who has kickstarted this “critical” metaphysical overview on history, stating that only the problem of “causation” (1940, p. 338-346)—having as a method the exam on the language—would be sufficient to sustain historiographical science. A good synthesis on the various contributions and debates around that “analytical metaphysics” about history can be found in Doris Gerber’s Analytische Metaphysik der Geschichte. Handlungen, Geschichten und ihre Erklärung (2012). For arguments about the insufficiency of analytical and critical philosophies of history and historiography, see Herman Paul (2015, p. 9-15). philosophies of history and historiography.5 5 The useful distinction between philosophy of history and philosophy of historiography is properly explained by Aviezer Tucker (2004).

The metaphysical claim about historicity through ontology

Since the publication of Hegel’s Phänomenologie des Geistes (1807), the ancient opposition between being and time has been challenged. Motivated by the incipient-but already relevant-modern historiography, Hegel, alongside Schelling, defined, from the standpoint of Kantian critique, the beginning of a historical metaphysics as an arrangement of elaborate inquiries into the role of time in the constitution of the human experience in relation to itself (the identity) and the Otherness that surrounds it (the difference). This manner of thinking starts from an assessment of “the historical,” i.e., the temporal character or sense of existence that relates time to being by means of its metaphysical theorems. Heidegger’s Sein und Zeit (1927) represents the strongest ontological elaboration directly connected with this tradition (DERRIDA, 2013DERRIDA, Jacques. Heidegger: la question de l’Être et l’Histoire. Cours de l’ENS-Ulm 1964-1965. Paris: Galilée, 2013., p. 50), according to which being exists only and as long as there is time, for being is a temporal fact; that is, being exists to the extent that it is no longer what it was and will be.

Especially since Heidegger’s work on historicity, therefore, historiology is no longer considered the apparent negation of ontology (ANGEHRN, 2019ANGEHRN, Emil. Sinn und Geschichte. Reflexionen zur historischen Ontologie. In: Prolegomena zur historischen Ontologie. Beiträge zur historischen Ontologie. Heidelberg: Winter, 2019. p. 25-36.). His approach, by developing a metaphysical doctrine of historicity, reveals the primitive aspect of historicism, which is the idea that supports epistemological propositions about the unique nature of each and every instant-the historical principle of Ranke (1954RANKE, Leopold von. Rankes Idee des Universalhistorie. Historische Zeitschrift, v. 178, n. 1, p. 209-308, 1954., p. 295; NIPPERDEY, 1975NIPPERDEY, Thomas. Historismus und Historismuskritik heute. [Historicism and the critics about historicism today]. In: JÄCKEL, Eberhard (ed.). Die Funktion der Geschichte in unserer Zeit. Stuttgart: Ernst Klett Verlag, 1975. p. 82-95., p. 84)-and to which modern historical science remains subject (FACKENHEIM, 1961FACKENHEIM, Emil. Metaphysics and Historicity. Milwaukee: Marquette University Press, 1961., p. 13). Beyond universalist historiography, Heidegger exposes the ontological foundation of the idea of historicism and the modern idea of history by scrutinizing the nature of time, stating that existence is [or can be] historical mainly because it is temporal (GA 2, 498HEIDEGGER, Martin. Gesamtausgabe. Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann, 1977-. [GA].). Time, a contradictory phenomenon that only exists when its existence is denied, is only as far as it is not anymore. That is, the non-being would be a necessary feature of what time is, the basis of the paradoxically perseverant contingent aspect of reality. It is in this sense that the finitude of individual and concrete existence-the fact of death-is the famous first step in Heidegger’s phenomenology toward the establishment of a principle about the nature of time that is not only epistemological, like Ranke’s, but also ontological.

Heidegger reaffirms the temporality of time expressly by saying that everything that exists has a beginning and an end. Meaning would reside in the end, in death, because the endpoint to existence formalizes a finite and understandable sense of the temporal experience (Cf. KERMODE, 2000KERMODE, Frank. The sense of an Ending. New York: Oxford University Press, 2000.). However, as a second step toward acknowledging the idea of historicity, Heidegger stresses ancient aporia on the ontology of time, particularly in relation to overcoming the finite limits of existence (GA 82, 230). That is, if time refers only to the limited aspects of individual existence, it becomes unclear how the reason or foundation of the historical phenomena could be justified or explained, which would involve, by definition, overcoming these very existential limits. History would be a phenomenon that expresses connections between common and differing existences and diverse spaces and times, thereby surpassing the physical limitations imposed by individual births and deaths, beginnings and ends.

Death completes its own course, but it does not mean the end of human existence. With death a transition begins from here ἐνθάδε [entháde] to there έχει [ékhei]. This transition is the beginning of a journey that takes place through the mortal passage towards the new περῐ́οδος θανατοφόρος [períodos thanatophóros]. The question that arises is the following: what surrounds humanity and what remains of it after its deadly and telluric course comes to an end? (GA 54, 143HEIDEGGER, Martin. Gesamtausgabe. Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann, 1977-. [GA].).

The theoretical answer to this question demonstrates that the historical is “what surrounds” and “what remains of humanity”-what, beyond the concrete, contingent, and finite, survives in the form of knowledge (ideas).6 6 See Augusto de Carvalho. Das potências da memória. A afirmação da transitoriedade histórica e da eternidade das ideias. Kriterion 61 (p. 107-129); See also Augusto de Carvalho, “The Meanings of Historicity—the End and the Beginning,” in Geschichtstheorie am Werk (2022). The historical, then, consists of all that survives or surpasses death, and the historical phenomena by means of this infinite nature of time reveals a principle according to which time is not restricted to the concrete temporality or the finitude of existence but exceeds these limits in a metaphysical way. Human existence is not, accordingly, reduced to the interval between birth and death, to what is called its presence, its Dasein, being limited to its physical and anthropological conditions; on the contrary, human existence is marked by overcoming birth and death by means of knowledge, the ideal aspects of existence.

Existence has a metaphysical feature that finds its roots in the phenomenon of time. This metaphysical aspect of reality in general or of human life in particular reveals some theoretical characteristics of history that can only be accessed from an “anti-naturalistic” perspective (Cf. GABRIEL, 2017GABRIEL, Markus. I Am Not a Brain. Cambridge: Polity Press, 2017.). The understanding of an event, a process, a phenomenon, or a life requires consideration of more than the interval between beginning and end. Rather, it is crucial to account for the previous meanings as well as the surviving meanings that pervade events, processes, phenomena, or lives. Such is the metaphysical basis of the historical regard: the historicity of existence.

In short, that restatement of metaphysics in the realm of philosophical thinking is one result of a broad process of questioning metaphysics itself by assuming the necessary ontological challenge of clarifying the roles of time and history in philosophical knowledge. Despite his repeated criticism of a certain form of metaphysics (ZAHAVI, 2008ZAHAVI, Dan. Phénoménologie et métaphysique. Les Études philosophiques, n. 87, p. 499-517, 2008.),7 7 Mainly in Was ist Metaphysik? And Die ontotheologische Verfassung der Metaphysik. Heidegger’s critique of metaphysics as onto-theo-logy (GA 11, 51-80) is a well-known topic of philosophy: a critique of metaphysics as the theological search for a single explanatory principle for everything. Heidegger remains a metaphysician (MÜLLER, 1949MÜLLER, Max. Existenzphilosophie im geistigen Leben der Gegenwart. [Philosophy of Existence in the present intellectual life]. Heidelberg: Kerle, 1949.) given his belief that “the fundamental ontology does not exhaust the concept of metaphysics” (GA 26, 199HEIDEGGER, Martin. Gesamtausgabe. Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann, 1977-. [GA].), at least to the extent that historicity summarizes the temporal character of concrete historical existence by means of an abstract metaphysical claim. According to Scholz, since the “historical sciences investigate the past and the development from the past to the present ... a metaphysics of time and change is required” (2014, p. 249). Heidegger provides, in this context, sophisticated metaphysical theorems about the historicity of reality stating not only that the time-like character of reality signifies the context that limits existence but also that historicity requires the acknowledgment that nothing comes from nothing-this being a primitive metaphysical principle about the pastness of what Heidegger calls Dasein, the presence, or existence, that is always in relation to time-like Otherness.

The metaphysics of contingency as a way to understand the meaning of historicity

Schelling did fundamental work on the task of understanding the temporal nature of reality from a historiological point of view. Taking a step back from Heidegger to understand more about what is at stake in the ontological theorems of historicity, Schelling helps to organize a metaphysics of contingency, that is, a theoretical justification of contingency as a reason, or “groundless ground” (BRUFF, 2018BRUFF, Kyla. The Implications of Schelling’s Metaphysics of Contingency for Phenomenology. The Official Journal of the North American Schelling Society, v. 1, p. 137-174, 2018.), for existence that, according to him, is found in the past as a principle. In so doing, Schelling shows that his “governing concern is to develop a set of intellectual (and aesthetic) tools to conceptualize and articulate the distinctive nature of the past” (WELCHMAN; NORMAN, 2010WELCHMAN, Alistair; NORMAN, Judith. Creating the Past: Schelling’s Ages of the World. Journal of the Philosophy of History, v. 4, p. 23-43, 2010., p. 42-43). In this specific sense, he is concerned with the same phenomenon that Heidegger finds in his investigations into the ontological relationship between being and time, namely, historicity. Particularly in the incomplete Die Weltalter, in which Schelling is essentially concerned with the human relationship with the past, he examines various temporal dimensions (Cf. GABRIEL, 2014GABRIEL, Markus. Die Zeitphilosophie in Schellings Weltaltern. Journal of International Philosophy, n. 5, p. 40-55, 2014., p. 41; WIRTZ, 2018WIRTZ, Fernando. Die Schichten der Zeit. Schellings Periodisierung der Geschichte und seine Kritik der homogenen Zeit im Rahmen seiner Philosophie der Mythologie. Schelling-Studien, v. 6, p. 43-62, 2018. ) and offers particular explanations of the source of contingency and the phenomena of passage and transience. The ages of the world, according to Schelling, are precisely its past, its present, and its future as dynamic experiences of the human spirit (SSW VIII, 234SCHELLING, F. W. J. Die Weltalter [The ages of the world]. In: Sämtliche Werke [VIII]. Stuttgart/Augsburg: Cotta, 1861. [SSW].). However, the past would be prominent as a special occurrence across the entire phenomenon of time, as it has a particular metaphysical and ontological quality, “in itself neither being nor non-being” (SCHELLING, 2002SCHELLING, F. W. J. Weltalter-Fragmente. [The ages of the world-Fragments]. Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt: Frommann-holzboog, 2002., 173). Accordingly, in the past, there is no present presence, no affirmation of being, nor a total absence of being as an absolute non-being, projected but still-non-existent, no not-yet imagined future, no categorical affirmation nor denial of existence. There is, rather, a mixture of shared and uncanny contradictory qualities, for the past would exist simultaneously as the being and non-being of time. Alternatively, it could still be said that, for the past, as a phenomenon, its presence is absent, and its absence is present once it is acknowledged. Though logically inconsistent, the phenomenal character of the past is, thereby, consistent with the very abstract nature of time in that it is contradictory by definition, consisting of both being and non-being (hence Schelling’s “in itself neither being nor non-being”). The past, then, displays these unique characteristics regarding temporal phenomena because it contains the elementary contradictory nature of time within itself.

Thus, for Schelling, “all life must pass through the fire of contradiction; contradiction is the engine and the core of life” (SSW VIII, 321SCHELLING, F. W. J. Die Weltalter [The ages of the world]. In: Sämtliche Werke [VIII]. Stuttgart/Augsburg: Cotta, 1861. [SSW].). The fundamental contradiction, time, identified in the past, corresponds to this “fire,” and all passage or contingency manifest, indeed, phenomena derived from the quality of “pastness” in time. By definition, the passage of time assumes the existence of the past. The notion that the past is the origin of the passage of time and is at the core of its contradictory essence thus supports Schelling’s notion “of ​​a beginning before the metaphysically understood origin” (GABRIEL, 2014GABRIEL, Markus. Die Zeitphilosophie in Schellings Weltaltern. Journal of International Philosophy, n. 5, p. 40-55, 2014., p. 44), a conceptual beginning for temporal phenomena with the past (not the present) as the image of contingency. Then, since any statement about the reality of time-or, more precisely, about the past-has originated in metaphysics, as Hilda OakeleyOAKELEY, Hilda. The Status of the Past. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, v. 32, n. 1, p. 227-250, 1932. asserted, “a proof of the existence of the past which may be called metaphysical . . . [is] derived from the fundamental fact of the passage” (1932, p. 242). Though not concretely demonstrable (THOMAS, 2015THOMAS, Emily. Hilda Oakeley on Idealism, History and the Real Past. British Journal for the History of Philosophy, v. 23, n. 5, p. 933-953, 2015., p. 949), a metaphysics of the past can, theoretically, postulate pastness, as the being and the non-being of time, as a phenomenon derived from the aforementioned basic temporal contradiction.

Briefly, Schelling helps to explain why history deals with the main feature of time, its contingency, and why history, while being epistemologically connected to individuality at the present presence of existence, extends beyond the limits of finite present beings owing to the uncanny virtues of the past. This past would be not a simple modus of time. It is rather the ontological explanation of the contingent reality that surpasses the limits of the presence of things, showing the presence of non-beings-the pasts-in what is called existence. Accordingly, historicity would be a result of the past’s fundamental nature as an expression of being and non-being reality, that is, through the acknowledgment of the past as a metaphysical (or ontological) principle. This principle is the minimum element of time that, alongside Ranke’s epistemological historical principle regarding the individuality of any phenomena, characterizes historical existence as simultaneously real, consistent, and contingent, inconsistent.

The metahistorical aspect of historicity

While Schelling’s contribution to the discussion of these issues is substantial, Hegel is the most important figure in and the basis of all criticism of philosophies of history, having remained at the center of a debate about philosophical identity in relation to the historical phenomena for “what came after Hegel was either derivative, or it was a rebellion of the philosophers [and historians] against philosophy in general, rebellion against or doubt of this identity” (ARENDT, 2002ARENDT, Hannah. What is Existenz Philosophie? In: MOONEY, T.; MORAN, D. (ed.). The Phenomenology Reader. London/New York: Routledge, 2002. p. 345-361., p. 345). By introducing the metaphysics of the contingent into philosophy and the ontology of existence into history, Hegel raises issues that are problematic from both perspectives.

Nevertheless, the most evident errors in Hegel’s historical thought are his propositions about the forms of historiography and several of his epistemological interpretations of the progressive nature of Weltgeschichte. In these propositions and interpretations, he postulates the controversial universalist principle of the impulse of perfectibility (Werke 12, 74CARR, David. On historicity. Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal, v. 37, p. 273-288, 2016.).8 8 I am referring to Hegel’s complete works [Werke] (1986), followed by volume and page number. In the Vorlesungen über die Philosophie der Weltgeschichte (1822-23), a clear example of the philosophical theologizing of history (Cf. LÖWITH, 1949LÖWITH, Karl. Meaning in History: The Theological Implications of the Philosophy of History. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1949.), he transposes elements of Christian messianism onto the broad and general modern idea of history. From an ethical-political point of view, then, Hegel is equally misguided in assuming a Eurocentric interpretation of his metaphysical system of world history in the Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts (1820), a work that describes, especially in its final paragraphs, the movement of the absolute Spirit (or history) as the exclusive march of Nordic and Germanic peoples, circumscribing the historian’s task within modern Europe. Hegel’s “hermeneutics of freedom,” according to Walter JaeschkeJAESCHKE, Walter. Hegel-Handbuch: Leben - Werk - Schule. [Hegel Handbook. Life - Work - School]. Stuttgart: J. B. Metzler Verlag, 2016., imposes on those who seek it the recognition of this progress of Western and Christian freedom as a global necessity (2016, p. 380).9 9 It is noteworthy that Klaus Vieweg (2020) recently have contested the accusation towards the “colonialist character” of Hegel’s thinking.

Despite these well-known ethical and epistemological problems with Hegel’s work, his reflections on and questions about the historical character of existence in relation to the human mind [Geist] remain relevant. In other words, while his philosophy of historiography should be treated with suspicion, his ontological investigation into the metaphysical ground of history has merit. No metahistorical process of recognition [Anerkennung] of the humanity of the human through the development of speculative identification through differentiation has yet received as fundamental an abstract and systematic exposition as the explanation that Hegel presents in his phenomenology-and, indeed, many have followed his basic scheme, from Karl Marx to Axel Honneth. The functioning of the remembrance process, the relationship between the ideal and concrete worlds (which surpasses ancient dualism), the demonstration of the historical character of thought itself, the metaphysics of time, contingence, and history developed by Schelling and Heidegger-all of these developments unquestionably trace back to Hegel. Hence, philosophies of historicity draw on Hegel to understand humanity, not in terms of evolutional progress, but as a “synthesis of need and freedom” (FERREIRA DA SILVA, 2009FERREIRA DA SILVA, Vicente. Dialética das Consciências. [Consciousness dialectics]. São Paulo: É Realizações, 2009., p. 111).

This return to Hegel is, then, necessary to reexamine the metaphysical centrality of the historicity of existence described by Schelling and, again, especially Heidegger after him. For Hegel, this historicity resides in the historical character of the re-memorization or re-interiorization [Er-innerung] (Werke 3, 590-91CARR, David. On historicity. Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal, v. 37, p. 273-288, 2016.) of all possible knowledge that is found in the historical-existential process of concreteness, which exists always with respect to a definite context. In that sense, according to Markus Gabriel, the current thinking in philosophical anthropology correctly establishes that “how we conceive of ourselves as human beings in part determines the moral value of our actions,” so there is, then, the need to “recognize fully that our essence as human beings is a function of the historical structure of our mind as Geist-i.e., of our capacity to create images of what it is to be human being and act in accordance with these images” (GABRIEL, 2017GABRIEL, Markus. I Am Not a Brain. Cambridge: Polity Press, 2017., p. 215).10 10 Markus Gabriel opposes this interpretation of historicity to Heidegger’s historicity (2017, 218). However, Gabriel’s historicity agrees substantially with Heidegger’s. For this reason, it is possible to establish a foundation for epistemological possibilities about knowledge as well as the power of political ideologies, for the various ethics of peoples, and for the cultural myriad that constitutes humanity. Such an approach does not deny the anthropological and naturalistic perspective but improves on it through a philosophy based on metaphysical arguments about history.

Clearly, none of this argumentation implies the existence of one moral and political “universal subject.” Nor does it mean that, from an anthropological perspective, some people are “savages”-those who have not yet recognized themselves as historical-and some are “civilized”-those who recognize themselves as historical.11 11 See the misunderstanding of Claude Lévi-Strauss on the problem of historicity (1962). David Carr shed light on this topic, stating that “perhaps we should conclude that [Levi-Strauss’] ‘peoples without history’ represent not the absence of historicity but another one of its forms.” (2016, p. 276). On the contrary, if a metaphysical and existential inquiry into history reveals anything, it is that humanity can assume multiple characteristics owing to the nature of its possibilities (Cf. GABRIEL, 2017GABRIEL, Markus. I Am Not a Brain. Cambridge: Polity Press, 2017., p. 213). Further, historical metaphysics doesn’t require the human mind to be a “poor abstraction” compared with the “rich[ness]” of anthropological and historical “diversity” (Cf. GRENE, 1978GRENE, Marjorie. The Paradoxes of Historicity. The Review of Metaphysics, v. 32, n. 1, p. 15-36, 1978., p. 20) since, by definition, it comprises many concrete minds. That is, a philosophy of historicity involves the discovery of humanity from a necessarily existential point of view for any and all human existence in relation to its Otherness (human and non-human). Contrary to Michel Foucault’s conclusion in Les mots et les choses (1966) that l’homme s’effacerait [the human will disappear], historical metaphysics reevaluates old questions by renewing the idea of humanity and avoiding misunderstandings between existing and its own becoming since the contingent aspect of reality has a shared metaphysical basis, namely, past time.

The philosophy of historicity as a metaphysical inquiry into history

Historical research never reveals “history,” for it always already carries an opinion about the meaning of “history” in an unreflective or supposed self-evident way; historical research only wishes to confirm what is already solidly confirmed by the research itself, showing the absence of thought about “history.” (GA 54, 142HEIDEGGER, Martin. Gesamtausgabe. Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann, 1977-. [GA].).12 12 See also GA 38, 94.

Heidegger argues that the writing of history does not discover its meaning. Nevertheless, it does assume one meaning for history. The essence, or what is presupposed by the idea of history, is determined only by the inquiry into the historical or temporal character of existence, that is, by a philosophy of historicity. Historiography, in this sense, involves considering time as an object always represented from a particular epistemological and ethical point of view. And, for that reason, historiography does not discover “the historical” (Cf. WALTON, 2019WALTON, Roberto J. El enraizamiento de la historicidad en el tiempo. Studia Heideggeriana, v. 7, p. 187-214, 2019.). Thus, a reflection on the historical character of existence occurs in the context of thinking about the historical, but not in its empirical conception in the form of historiography. Not even through the history of historiography can the metaphysical meaning of what is history be disclosed.13 13 Valdei Araujo clarifies the history of historiography as “the analytic of historicity” (2013). It was an important step forward for the existential acknowledgment of historiography. The fulfillment of this task requires asking, in an honest and direct way, what history means, why there is history, and in what ways history exists. These interrogations, roughly, are found not in historiographical investigations, but in existential, ontological, and, above all, metaphysical questions about the being of history, “a theory about history” (SIMON, 2019SIMON, Zoltán B. Do Theorists of History Have a Theory of History? Reflections on a Non-Discipline. História da Historiografia, v. 12, n. 29, p. 53-68, 2019., p. 60), which means a philosophy of historicity.

According to ManelMANEL, Frank. In Defense of Philosophical History. The Antioch Review, v. 20, n. 3, p. 331-343, 1960., “some are afraid that the philosophers of history might seduce us into bad habits. Granted. They are as dangerous to the development of the historian as poets and novelists, and they are as vital to his existence” (1960, p. 343). That is, the choice of a more anthropological and concrete approach to historical reality, though relevant to historiographical research, does not obviate other questions about the abstract nature of the phenomenon of history but, in fact, enables new paths for new questions. Accordingly, to understand history as a phenomenon and the historical character of existence as an expression of the inconsistent and contradictory reality of time, a methodological question must be asked regarding what it means to be a temporal being.

Certainly, none of these considerations suggest that philosophers are better able to write history (RICŒUR, 1985RICŒUR, Paul. Temps et Récit (III). [Time and narrative]. Paris: Éditions du Seuil, 1985., p. 350) than historians. The point is, rather, that there is no way to avoid or renounce14 14 A reference to the well-known chapter from Temps et Récit (1985), “Renoncer à Hegel.” a philosophy of historicity as a metaphysical path to address questions that, because of the restricted scope of conventional epistemology, philosophies of history and historiography are not able to answer. A philosophy of historicity is required, then, to understand the still often neglected ontological assumptions embedded in history and historiography.

References

  • ANGEHRN, Emil. Sinn und Geschichte. Reflexionen zur historischen Ontologie. In: Prolegomena zur historischen Ontologie. Beiträge zur historischen Ontologie Heidelberg: Winter, 2019. p. 25-36.
  • ANKERSMIT, Frank. 2012. Meaning, Truth and Reference in Historical Representation New York: Cornell University Press, 2012.
  • ARAUJO, Valdei. História da historiografia como analítica da historicidade. História da Historiografia, v. 6, n. 12, p. 34-44, 2013.
  • ARENDT, Hannah. What is Existenz Philosophie? In: MOONEY, T.; MORAN, D. (ed.). The Phenomenology Reader London/New York: Routledge, 2002. p. 345-361.
  • BAUER, Gerhard. Geschichtlichkeit: Wege und Irrwege eines Begriffs. [Historicity: ways and wanderings of a concept]. Berlin: de Gruyter, 1963.
  • BEVERNAGE, Berber. From Philosophy of History to Philosophy of Historicities: Some Ideas on a Potential Future of Historical Theory. BMGN Low Countries Historical Review, v. 127-4, p. 113-120, 2012.
  • BRUFF, Kyla. The Implications of Schelling’s Metaphysics of Contingency for Phenomenology. The Official Journal of the North American Schelling Society, v. 1, p. 137-174, 2018.
  • CARR, David. On historicity. Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal, v. 37, p. 273-288, 2016.
  • CHAKRABARTY, Dipesh. The Future of the Human Sciences in the Age of Humans: A Note. European Journal of Social Theory, v. 20, n. 1, p. 39-43, 2017.
  • COLLINGWOOD, R. G. An Essay on Metaphysics London: Oxford, 1940.
  • DE CARVALHO, Augusto. A Brief History of Historicity. O que nos faz pensar, v. 30, n. 50, p. 196-221, 2022.
  • DERRIDA, Jacques. Heidegger: la question de l’Être et l’Histoire. Cours de l’ENS-Ulm 1964-1965. Paris: Galilée, 2013.
  • FACKENHEIM, Emil. Metaphysics and Historicity Milwaukee: Marquette University Press, 1961.
  • FERREIRA DA SILVA, Vicente. Dialética das Consciências [Consciousness dialectics]. São Paulo: É Realizações, 2009.
  • GABRIEL, Markus. Die Zeitphilosophie in Schellings Weltaltern. Journal of International Philosophy, n. 5, p. 40-55, 2014.
  • GABRIEL, Markus. I Am Not a Brain Cambridge: Polity Press, 2017.
  • GERBER, Doris. Analytische Metaphysik der Geschichte: Handlungen, Geschichten und ihre Erklärung. [Analytical Philosophy of History. Actions, histories and its explanations]. Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp, 2012.
  • GRENE, Marjorie. The Paradoxes of Historicity. The Review of Metaphysics, v. 32, n. 1, p. 15-36, 1978.
  • HEGEL, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. Werke Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1986.
  • HEIDEGGER, Martin. Gesamtausgabe Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann, 1977-. [GA].
  • JAESCHKE, Walter. Hegel-Handbuch: Leben - Werk - Schule. [Hegel Handbook. Life - Work - School]. Stuttgart: J. B. Metzler Verlag, 2016.
  • JORDHEIM, Helge. Against Periodization: Koselleck’s Theory of Multiple Temporalities. History and Theory, v. 51, n. 2, p. 151-171, 2012.
  • KERMODE, Frank. The sense of an Ending New York: Oxford University Press, 2000.
  • KOSLOWSKI, Peter. The Discovery of Historicity in German Idealism and Historism Berlin, Heidelberg, New York: Springer, 2005.
  • KUKI, Shūzō. Gūzensei no Mondai [The question of contingency]. Tokyo: Iwanami Bunko, 2012.
  • LANDWEHR, Achim. Von der, Gleichzeitigkeit des Ungleichzeitigen’. Historische Zeitschrift, v. 295, n. 1, p. 1-34, 2012.
  • LÉVI-STRAUSS, Claude. La Pensée sauvage Paris: Agora, 1962.
  • LÖWITH, Karl. Meaning in History: The Theological Implications of the Philosophy of History. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1949.
  • LYOTARD, J-F. La Phénoménologie Paris: PUF, 1954.
  • MANEL, Frank. In Defense of Philosophical History. The Antioch Review, v. 20, n. 3, p. 331-343, 1960.
  • MCTAGGART, J. M. E. The Unreality of Time. Mind, v. 17, n. 68, p. 457-474, 1908.
  • MUDROVCIC, María Inés. Time, History, and Philosophy of History. Journal of the Philosophy of History, v. 8, n. 2, p. 217-242, 2014.
  • MÜLLER, Max. Existenzphilosophie im geistigen Leben der Gegenwart [Philosophy of Existence in the present intellectual life]. Heidelberg: Kerle, 1949.
  • NIPPERDEY, Thomas. Historismus und Historismuskritik heute. [Historicism and the critics about historicism today]. In: JÄCKEL, Eberhard (ed.). Die Funktion der Geschichte in unserer Zeit Stuttgart: Ernst Klett Verlag, 1975. p. 82-95.
  • OAKELEY, Hilda. The Status of the Past. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, v. 32, n. 1, p. 227-250, 1932.
  • PAUL, Herman. Key Issues in Historical Theory New York: Routledge, 2015.
  • RANKE, Leopold von. Rankes Idee des Universalhistorie. Historische Zeitschrift, v. 178, n. 1, p. 209-308, 1954.
  • RICŒUR, Paul. Temps et Récit (III) [Time and narrative]. Paris: Éditions du Seuil, 1985.
  • SCHELLING, F. W. J. Die Weltalter [The ages of the world]. In: Sämtliche Werke [VIII] Stuttgart/Augsburg: Cotta, 1861. [SSW].
  • SCHELLING, F. W. J. Weltalter-Fragmente [The ages of the world-Fragments]. Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt: Frommann-holzboog, 2002.
  • SCHOLZ, Oliver. Philosophy of History: Metaphysics and Epistemology. In: KAISER, M. I. et al (ed.). Explanation in the Special Sciences: The Case of Biology and History (Synthese Library). Dordrecht: Springer, 2014. p. 245-253.
  • SILVA, Diogo C. P. Kuki Shūzō’s Redefinition of Metaphysics Through Contingency. International Journal of the Philosophical Association of Japan, v. 3, p. 190-206, 2019.
  • SIMON, Zoltán B. Do Theorists of History Have a Theory of History? Reflections on a Non-Discipline. História da Historiografia, v. 12, n. 29, p. 53-68, 2019.
  • SOLOMYAK, Olla. Temporal Ontology and the Metaphysics of Perspectives. Erkenntnis, v. 85, p. 431-453, 2018.
  • THOMAS, Emily. Hilda Oakeley on Idealism, History and the Real Past. British Journal for the History of Philosophy, v. 23, n. 5, p. 933-953, 2015.
  • TUCKER, Aviezer. Our knowledge of the past: A philosophy of historiography. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004.
  • TURIN, Rodrigo. Tempos precários: aceleração, historicidade e semântica neoliberal. Dansk: Zazie Edições, 2019.
  • VIEWEG, Klaus. Hegel als Denker des Kolonialismus? [Hegel as a thinker of colonialism?]. Philosophie Magazin, 2020. Available from: https://www.philomag.de/artikel/hegel-als-denker-des-kolonialismus Access in: 11 feb. 2022.
    » https://www.philomag.de/artikel/hegel-als-denker-des-kolonialismus
  • VON RENTHE-FINK, Leonhard. “Geschichtlichkeit [Historicity].” In: RITTER, Joachim et al (ed.). Historisches Wörterbuch der Philosophie [3] Basel: Schwabe, 1974. p. 404-408.
  • WALTON, Roberto J. El enraizamiento de la historicidad en el tiempo. Studia Heideggeriana, v. 7, p. 187-214, 2019.
  • WELCHMAN, Alistair; NORMAN, Judith. Creating the Past: Schelling’s Ages of the World. Journal of the Philosophy of History, v. 4, p. 23-43, 2010.
  • WHITEHEAD, A. N. Process and Reality New York: The Free Press, 1978.
  • WIRTZ, Fernando. Die Schichten der Zeit. Schellings Periodisierung der Geschichte und seine Kritik der homogenen Zeit im Rahmen seiner Philosophie der Mythologie. Schelling-Studien, v. 6, p. 43-62, 2018.
  • ZAHAVI, Dan. Phénoménologie et métaphysique. Les Études philosophiques, n. 87, p. 499-517, 2008.

NOTAS

  • 1
    See Augusto de Carvalho. A lógica do tempo e de outras palavras fundamentais. Trans/Form/Ação 43/3, 2020. (p. 187-192)
  • 2
    See, for instance, McTaggart’s arguments (1908MCTAGGART, J. M. E. The Unreality of Time. Mind, v. 17, n. 68, p. 457-474, 1908.).
  • 3
    In a way, this essay responds to Bevernage (2012BEVERNAGE, Berber. From Philosophy of History to Philosophy of Historicities: Some Ideas on a Potential Future of Historical Theory. BMGN Low Countries Historical Review, v. 127-4, p. 113-120, 2012.) proposition, but from a speculative or philosophical standpoint.
  • 4
    It is worthy to note that R. G. CollingwoodCOLLINGWOOD, R. G. An Essay on Metaphysics. London: Oxford, 1940. was one of the firsts who has kickstarted this “critical” metaphysical overview on history, stating that only the problem of “causation” (1940, p. 338-346)—having as a method the exam on the language—would be sufficient to sustain historiographical science. A good synthesis on the various contributions and debates around that “analytical metaphysics” about history can be found in Doris Gerber’s Analytische Metaphysik der Geschichte. Handlungen, Geschichten und ihre Erklärung (2012GERBER, Doris. Analytische Metaphysik der Geschichte: Handlungen, Geschichten und ihre Erklärung. [Analytical Philosophy of History. Actions, histories and its explanations]. Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp, 2012.). For arguments about the insufficiency of analytical and critical philosophies of history and historiography, see Herman Paul (2015PAUL, Herman. Key Issues in Historical Theory. New York: Routledge, 2015., p. 9-15).
  • 5
    The useful distinction between philosophy of history and philosophy of historiography is properly explained by Aviezer Tucker (2004TUCKER, Aviezer. Our knowledge of the past: A philosophy of historiography. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004.).
  • 6
    See Augusto de Carvalho. Das potências da memória. A afirmação da transitoriedade histórica e da eternidade das ideias. Kriterion 61 (p. 107-129); See also Augusto de Carvalho, “The Meanings of Historicity—the End and the Beginning,” in Geschichtstheorie am Werk (2022DE CARVALHO, Augusto. A Brief History of Historicity. O que nos faz pensar, v. 30, n. 50, p. 196-221, 2022. ).
  • 7
    Mainly in Was ist Metaphysik? And Die ontotheologische Verfassung der Metaphysik. Heidegger’s critique of metaphysics as onto-theo-logy (GA 11, 51-80) is a well-known topic of philosophy: a critique of metaphysics as the theological search for a single explanatory principle for everything.
  • 8
    I am referring to Hegel’s complete works [Werke] (1986HEGEL, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. Werke. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1986.), followed by volume and page number.
  • 9
    It is noteworthy that Klaus Vieweg (2020VIEWEG, Klaus. Hegel als Denker des Kolonialismus? [Hegel as a thinker of colonialism?]. Philosophie Magazin, 2020. Available from: https://www.philomag.de/artikel/hegel-als-denker-des-kolonialismus . Access in: 11 feb. 2022.
    https://www.philomag.de/artikel/hegel-al...
    ) recently have contested the accusation towards the “colonialist character” of Hegel’s thinking.
  • 10
    Markus GabrielGABRIEL, Markus. I Am Not a Brain. Cambridge: Polity Press, 2017. opposes this interpretation of historicity to Heidegger’s historicity (2017, 218). However, Gabriel’s historicity agrees substantially with Heidegger’s.
  • 11
    See the misunderstanding of Claude Lévi-Strauss on the problem of historicity (1962LÉVI-STRAUSS, Claude. La Pensée sauvage. Paris: Agora, 1962.). David CarrCARR, David. On historicity. Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal, v. 37, p. 273-288, 2016. shed light on this topic, stating that “perhaps we should conclude that [Levi-Strauss’] ‘peoples without history’ represent not the absence of historicity but another one of its forms.” (2016, p. 276).
  • 12
    See also GA 38, 94.
  • 13
    Valdei Araujo clarifies the history of historiography as “the analytic of historicity” (2013ARAUJO, Valdei. História da historiografia como analítica da historicidade. História da Historiografia, v. 6, n. 12, p. 34-44, 2013.). It was an important step forward for the existential acknowledgment of historiography.
  • 14
    A reference to the well-known chapter from Temps et Récit (1985), “Renoncer à Hegel.”

Edited by

Editores:

Karina Anhezini e Eduardo Romero de Oliveira

Publication Dates

  • Publication in this collection
    11 Dec 2023
  • Date of issue
    2023

History

  • Received
    18 May 2023
  • Accepted
    08 Oct 2023
Universidade Estadual Paulista Julio de Mesquita Filho Faculdade de Ciências e Letras, UNESP, Campus de Assis, 19 806-900 - Assis - São Paulo - Brasil, Tel: (55 18) 3302-5861, Faculdade de Ciências Humanas e Sociais, UNESP, Campus de Franca, 14409-160 - Franca - São Paulo - Brasil, Tel: (55 16) 3706-8700 - Assis/Franca - SP - Brazil
E-mail: revistahistoria@unesp.br