Acessibilidade / Reportar erro

Causality in Pharmacoepidemiology and Pharmacovigilance: a theoretical excursion

ABSTRACT:

The article presents some considerations about causality in Pharmacoepidemiology and Pharmacovigilance. To begin, we provide a brief introduction about the importance of the issue, noting that the understanding of causal relationships is considered one of science’s greatest achievements and has been, over time, a continuous and central concern of philosophers and epidemiologists. Next, we describe definitions and types of causes, demonstrating their influences on pharmacoepidemiological thought. After that, we present Rothman’s multi-causal model as one of the founding explanations of multiple causality and the issue of causality assessment. We conclude with some comments and reflections on causality from the perspective of health surveillance, particularly with regard to regulations on pharmacovigilance.

Keywords:
Uses of epidemiology; Causality; Drug-related side effects and adverse reactions; Pharmacoepidemiology; Pharmacovigilance; Health surveillance

RESUMO:

O artigo teceu algumas considerações sobre causalidade em farmacoepidemiologia e farmacovigilância. Inicialmente, fizemos uma breve introdução sobre a importância do tema, ressaltando que o entendimento da relação causal é considerado como uma das maiores conquistas das ciências e que tem sido, ao longo dos tempos, uma preocupação contínua e central de filósofos e epidemiologistas. Na sequência, descrevemos as definições e os tipos de causas, demonstrando suas influências no pensamento farmacoepidemiológico. Logo a seguir, apresentamos o modelo multicausal de Rothman como um dos fundantes para a explicação da causalidade múltipla, e o tema da determinação da causalidade. Concluímos com alguns comentários e reflexões sobre causalidade na perspectiva da vigilância sanitária, particularmente, para as ações de regulação em farmacovigilância.

Palavras-chave:
Aplicações da epidemiologia; Causalidade; Efeitos colaterais e reações adversas relacionados a medicamentos; Farmacoepidemiologia; Farmacovigilância; Vigilância sanitária

INTRODUCTION

Drug use is related to the occurrence of adverse events (adverse drug events - ADE), which, by definition, include health problems resulting from the exposure to medications1 and are a frequent cause of hospitalization and death22. Carrasco-Garrido P, de Andrés LA, Barrera VH, de Miguel GA, Jiménez-García R. Trends of adverse drug reactions related-hospitalizations in Spain (2001-2006). BMC Health Serv Res. BioMed Central. 2010;10(1):287.,33. Mota DM, Melo JRR, Freitas DRC De, Machado M. Perfil da mortalidade por intoxicação com medicamentos no Brasil, 1996-2005: retrato de uma década. Ciên Saúde Colet. 2012;17(1):61-70.. One of the objectives of pharmacoepidemiology and pharmacovigilance is to identify and gather consistent evidence on the associations between drug use and the occurrence of adverse events. Such evidence grounds decision-making processes with regard to health surveillance.

The use of consistent evidence presupposes that causality inferences can be designed by examining the etiological link between drug exposer and an adverse event44. Bégaud B. Dictionary of pharmacopidemiology. Chichester: John Wiley & Sons; 2000. 171p.. Deterining causality presupposes an association between at least two phenomena and, in a simplified way, consists of answering the following question: Is (or would) the factor F a cause the adverse event E? This question assumes a temporal relation in which exposure precedes occurrence of the event44. Bégaud B. Dictionary of pharmacopidemiology. Chichester: John Wiley & Sons; 2000. 171p., and the supposed causal relation is reinforced by the frequency of such observation55. Edwards IR. Considerations on causality in pharmacovigilance. Int J Risk Saf Med. 2012;24:41-54..

The understanding of causality is regarded as one of science’s greatest achievements66. Bhopal R. Concepts of epidemiology: an integrated introduction to the ideas, theories, principles and methods of epidemiology. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2002. 639p. and has been, over time, a continuing concern of both philosophers and epidemiologists. The former have devoted themselves to studying the fundamental meaning of the notion of cause and the general principles of causality, while epidemiologists are interested in the identification of causes, in the quantification and characterization of effects, in the design causal models, and in examples of cause and effect relationships77. Holland P. Statistics and causal inference. J Am Stat Assoc. 1986;81:945-60.,88. Parascandola M, Weed DL. Causation in epidemiology. J Epidemiol Community Health. 2001;55:905-12.,99. Broadbent A. Philosophy of Epidemiology. Johannesburg: Palgrave Macmillan; 2013. 228p.. For Bhopal (2002, p.98)66. Bhopal R. Concepts of epidemiology: an integrated introduction to the ideas, theories, principles and methods of epidemiology. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2002. 639p., the purpose of studying causality in epidemiology is to produce knowledge on the prevention, cure, treatment and control of diseases and other health problems.

This article aimed to present considerations on one of the main conceptual and methodological challenges in pharmacoepidemiology and pharmacovigilance: the causal relationships between drugs and adverse events. It emphasizes the definition of causes and their types, Rothman’s multi-causal model1010. Rothman KJ. Causes. Am J Epidemiol. 1976;104(6):587-92., the determination of causality, and the causal relationship from the perspective of sanitary surveillance. It does not intend to exhaust the subject nor reach a consensus on the presented content, but rather to contribute to an initial sketch of causality in pharmacoepidemiology and pharmacovigilance, while trying to connect it to the practices of sanitary surveillance.

THE DEFINITION OF CAUSE

Hume, in the eighteenth century, wrote that causes are invariably followed by their effects1111. Hitchcock C. Probabilistic causation [internet]. 2012 [cited 2014 Dec. 13]. Available from: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/causation-probabilistic/#CauMarCon
http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/causat...
. In contemporary epidemiological thought, Rothman1010. Rothman KJ. Causes. Am J Epidemiol. 1976;104(6):587-92. defines cause as an act, event or a state of nature that initiates or permits, alone or in conjunction with other causes, a sequence of events that result in an effect. Susser1212. Susser M. What is a cause and how do we know one - A Grammar of Causality. Am J Epidemiol. 1991;133(7):635-48. resorts to Hume to propose essential properties in the recognition of cause that are fundamental to infer causality:

  1. there must be an association (cause and effect occur together);

  2. temporal order (cause precedes effect);

  3. connection or direction (links between cause and effect can be predicted) 1212. Susser M. What is a cause and how do we know one - A Grammar of Causality. Am J Epidemiol. 1991;133(7):635-48.,1313. Susser M. Glossary: causality in public health science. J Epidemiol Community Health. 2001;55:376-8..

Rothman and Greenland1414. Rothman KJ, Greenland S. Modern Epidemiology. 2ª ed. Philadelphia: Lippincott-Raven; 1998. incorporate the dimension of temporality into the definition of cause: a cause of a disease is an event, condition or characteristic that preceded the illness and without which the disease would not have occurred at all. For Bhopal, cause is comprised of something that alters the frequency of the disease, health status or associated factors in the population66. Bhopal R. Concepts of epidemiology: an integrated introduction to the ideas, theories, principles and methods of epidemiology. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2002. 639p..

No definition of the term “cause” was found in didactic materials on pharmacoepidemiology44. Bégaud B. Dictionary of pharmacopidemiology. Chichester: John Wiley & Sons; 2000. 171p.,1515. Laporte JR, Tognoni G. Principios de epidemiología del medicamento. 2ª ed. Barcelona: Masson; 1993. 280p.,1616. Carvajal García-Pando A. Farmacoepidemiología. Valladolid: Secretariado de Publicaciones, Universida, D.L.; 1993. 162p.,1717. Kennedy DL, Goldman SA, Lillie RB. Spontaneous reporting in the United States. In: Strom BL, editor. Pharmacoepidemiology. 3ª ed. New York: John Willy & Sons; 2000. p. 151-74.,1818. Yang Y, West-Strum D. Compreendendo a farmacoepidemiologia. Porto Alegre: AMGH; 2013. 198p.,1919. Coelho HLL, Santos DB. Farmacoepidemiologia. In: Almeida Filho N, Barreto ML, Eds. Epidemiologia & Saúde - Fundamentos, métodos e aplicações. Rio de Janeiro: Guanabara Koogan; 2011. p. 670-7.. The omission may be related to the difficulty in defining a cause in the context of determining the causality between medication and an adverse event, since, in general, it may involve a mixture of causes, and it is therefore preferable not to speak of “causes”, but rather of “risk factors”1515. Laporte JR, Tognoni G. Principios de epidemiología del medicamento. 2ª ed. Barcelona: Masson; 1993. 280p. or “association factors”1818. Yang Y, West-Strum D. Compreendendo a farmacoepidemiologia. Porto Alegre: AMGH; 2013. 198p.,1919. Coelho HLL, Santos DB. Farmacoepidemiologia. In: Almeida Filho N, Barreto ML, Eds. Epidemiologia & Saúde - Fundamentos, métodos e aplicações. Rio de Janeiro: Guanabara Koogan; 2011. p. 670-7.. Both terms do not necessarily imply a causal relationship. Another possible explanation is that causality, not the elements that compose it (cause and effect), is a topic studied and prioritized in the chapters on methods used in pharmacoepidemiology and pharmacovigilance1515. Laporte JR, Tognoni G. Principios de epidemiología del medicamento. 2ª ed. Barcelona: Masson; 1993. 280p.,1818. Yang Y, West-Strum D. Compreendendo a farmacoepidemiologia. Porto Alegre: AMGH; 2013. 198p.,1919. Coelho HLL, Santos DB. Farmacoepidemiologia. In: Almeida Filho N, Barreto ML, Eds. Epidemiologia & Saúde - Fundamentos, métodos e aplicações. Rio de Janeiro: Guanabara Koogan; 2011. p. 670-7., although the definition of what is a cause has been the source of discussion by epidemiologists1313. Susser M. Glossary: causality in public health science. J Epidemiol Community Health. 2001;55:376-8.,1414. Rothman KJ, Greenland S. Modern Epidemiology. 2ª ed. Philadelphia: Lippincott-Raven; 1998..

TYPES OF CAUSES

Parascandola and Weed88. Parascandola M, Weed DL. Causation in epidemiology. J Epidemiol Community Health. 2001;55:905-12. found five different definitions of the types of causes in the area of epidemiology: production, necessary, component-sufficient, probabilistic, and counterfactual causes.

The definition of cause production presupposes that a cause “creates” or “produces” effects, giving rise to an “ontological distinction” between causal and non-causal associations, even though this characterization is somewhat vague in the author’s own view88. Parascandola M, Weed DL. Causation in epidemiology. J Epidemiol Community Health. 2001;55:905-12.. The necessary cause depicts a condition without which the effect will not occur. On the other hand, its presence does not result unequivocally in the occurrence of the event44. Bégaud B. Dictionary of pharmacopidemiology. Chichester: John Wiley & Sons; 2000. 171p.,88. Parascandola M, Weed DL. Causation in epidemiology. J Epidemiol Community Health. 2001;55:905-12.. The view that causes must be necessary for the occurrence of their effects is traditionally associated with germ theory, in which there is the assumption that the disease is motivated by at least one specific infectious agent88. Parascandola M, Weed DL. Causation in epidemiology. J Epidemiol Community Health. 2001;55:905-12.. Such a situation is rare within the drug-adverse event causal relationship, and examples such as gray baby syndrome following the use of chloramphenicol are difficult to find in clinical practice55. Edwards IR. Considerations on causality in pharmacovigilance. Int J Risk Saf Med. 2012;24:41-54..

Some causes are necessary - though not sufficient - for the occurrence of a disease. One explanation for this is that the name of some syndromes or diseases is defined by the triggering exposure, that is, the causal agent2020. Lagiou P, Adami HO, Trichopoulos D. Causality in cancer epidemiology. Eur J Epidemiol. 2005;20:565-74.. Thus, berylliosis can not occur in the absence of exposure to beryllium,2020. Lagiou P, Adami HO, Trichopoulos D. Causality in cancer epidemiology. Eur J Epidemiol. 2005;20:565-74. and the framing of a problem such as ADE requires that a drug has been used. For example, in various diagnostic codes of the International Classification of Diseases (ICD-10)2121. Organização Mundial da Saúde. Classificação Estatística Internacional de Doenças e Problemas Relacionados à Saúde. 10a ed. São Paulo: Editora da USP; 2012., the drug is identified in the description of the clinical problem.

One of the limitations experienced by the process of causal inference in pharmacoepidemiology and pharmacovigilance is that some diseases have causal factors without a defined component as a necessary cause. In a series of cases of fulminant hepatitis, depending on the epidemiological situation, it can not be stated that all occurrences are related to a drug, since other agents such as hepatitis A or B viruses and cytomegalovirus are also triggers of this health problem2222. Vineis P. Causality in epidemiology. Soz-Präventivmed. 2003;48:80-7.. In most situations the “drug” cause for a given adverse event is competing or perhaps interacting with several other possible causes55. Edwards IR. Considerations on causality in pharmacovigilance. Int J Risk Saf Med. 2012;24:41-54..

The definition of a component-sufficient cause was proposed by Rothman1010. Rothman KJ. Causes. Am J Epidemiol. 1976;104(6):587-92. and expands the view of the necessary cause, although it retains a similar deterministic scientific language88. Parascandola M, Weed DL. Causation in epidemiology. J Epidemiol Community Health. 2001;55:905-12.. Component-sufficient causes are composed of a number of component causes that, alone, are not sufficient for the occurrence of the adverse event. A set of component causes constitutes a sufficient cause, ensuring the occurrence of the event in question88. Parascandola M, Weed DL. Causation in epidemiology. J Epidemiol Community Health. 2001;55:905-12..

The main characteristic of the probabilistic causes is that they increase the possibility of the occurrence of their effects, that is, C causes E if, and only if, C increases the probability of the occurrence of E88. Parascandola M, Weed DL. Causation in epidemiology. J Epidemiol Community Health. 2001;55:905-12.. The probabilistic cause does not need to be necessary or sufficient, nor does it exclude the necessary and sufficient causes. Its definition is broader than that of a component-sufficient cause88. Parascandola M, Weed DL. Causation in epidemiology. J Epidemiol Community Health. 2001;55:905-12..

Finally, a counterfactual cause is the difference in the result - or the probability of the result - when it is present compared to when it is absent, that is, it is the result of T minus the absence of T88. Parascandola M, Weed DL. Causation in epidemiology. J Epidemiol Community Health. 2001;55:905-12.. It compares the frequency of the occurrence of observed outcomes among exposed individuals compared to those that were not exposed, ensuring comparability. Counterfactuality is explored from experimental and observational studies, and in the latter, the presence of residual confounding does not always allow for unambiguous inferences of cause and effect to be established.

The definition of probabilistic cause combined with the counterfactual condition provides better substrate in pharmacoepidemiology88. Parascandola M, Weed DL. Causation in epidemiology. J Epidemiol Community Health. 2001;55:905-12.. That is, C causes E if the probability of E - in the presence of C - is greater than that of E in the absence of C, under conditions that ensure comparability88. Parascandola M, Weed DL. Causation in epidemiology. J Epidemiol Community Health. 2001;55:905-12.. An example of the probabilistic-counterfactual combination is the tetanus vaccine (TT), which causes Guillain-Barré syndrome (GBS) with limb paralysis if the probability P (GBS | TT). As such, the probability of GBS in the presence of TT is greater than that of GBS in the absence of TT - this, in ceteris paribus conditions55. Edwards IR. Considerations on causality in pharmacovigilance. Int J Risk Saf Med. 2012;24:41-54.. These requirements simplify the causal structure, giving opportunities for the acceptance of the probabilistic-counterfactual combination2323. Aguiar T. Hempel: a teoria da explicação científica. In: Aguiar T. Causalidade e direção do tempo: Hume e o debate contemporâneo. Belo Horizonte: Editora UFMG; 2008. p. 177..

In the perspective of pharmacovigilance, Edwards55. Edwards IR. Considerations on causality in pharmacovigilance. Int J Risk Saf Med. 2012;24:41-54. also defines two types of causes to explain the possible ways in which they can act:

  1. Contributory causes: actively involved in the adding of an effect, such as a relative overdose or drug interactions;

  2. Contingent causes: essential for the occurrence of the effect, but which have no causal effect per se and which may be unknown, such as a particular cytochromometabolic enzyme phenotype that makes certain patients more susceptible to the effects of a drug.

The former are possibly intrinsic and influence other causes, but are not necessary, like the long half-life of a drug. They can be modified, influencing the causal relation, while the contingents cannot be altered.

They are also rarely routinely investigated in pharmacovigilance practices, as the emphasis is often on the drug as a possible cause rather than on other contributory causes, as is the case with medication errors55. Edwards IR. Considerations on causality in pharmacovigilance. Int J Risk Saf Med. 2012;24:41-54..

There is still another typology of causes in the epidemiological literature that is based on the processes of health determination, which presuppose causal determinants, characterizing them as distal (structural or socioeconomic), intermediary (behavioral characteristics, for example) and proximal (biological characteristics, for example) causes. In the accidental intoxication of children, the drug would be classified as a proximal cause, while the omission of sanitary legislation on safety systems in drug packaging would be framed as distal.

Bégaud’s44. Bégaud B. Dictionary of pharmacopidemiology. Chichester: John Wiley & Sons; 2000. 171p. pharmacoepidemiological dictionary defines two types of cause: necessary and sufficient. Laporte and Tognoni’s1515. Laporte JR, Tognoni G. Principios de epidemiología del medicamento. 2ª ed. Barcelona: Masson; 1993. 280p. book, a reference in the area of pharmacoepidemiology and pharmacovigilance, makes no mention of the types of causes addressed in this article. This finding was also verified in other books on pharmacoepidemiology1616. Carvajal García-Pando A. Farmacoepidemiología. Valladolid: Secretariado de Publicaciones, Universida, D.L.; 1993. 162p.,1717. Kennedy DL, Goldman SA, Lillie RB. Spontaneous reporting in the United States. In: Strom BL, editor. Pharmacoepidemiology. 3ª ed. New York: John Willy & Sons; 2000. p. 151-74.,1818. Yang Y, West-Strum D. Compreendendo a farmacoepidemiologia. Porto Alegre: AMGH; 2013. 198p.,1919. Coelho HLL, Santos DB. Farmacoepidemiologia. In: Almeida Filho N, Barreto ML, Eds. Epidemiologia & Saúde - Fundamentos, métodos e aplicações. Rio de Janeiro: Guanabara Koogan; 2011. p. 670-7..

The definitions and types of causes have influenced pharmacoepidemiological thinking on causality66. Bhopal R. Concepts of epidemiology: an integrated introduction to the ideas, theories, principles and methods of epidemiology. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2002. 639p., promoting the design of causal models, such as the multicausal approach proposed by Rothman1010. Rothman KJ. Causes. Am J Epidemiol. 1976;104(6):587-92.. The mapping of the different causes, including typifying them in the context of a causal structure under sanitary investigation, can facilitate the identification of the causes that are essential in the maintenance of the problem. Identification makes the planning and prioritization of regulatory corrective actions in pharmacovigilance more efficient, since as the causal structure is broken, the event can be reduced, eliminated or prevented2424. Krieger N. Epidemiology and the web of causation: Has anyone seen the spider? Soc Sci Med. 1994;39(7):887-903..

ROTHMAN’S MULTI-CAUSAL MODEL

Epidemiologists have sought to construct causal models in attempts to understand and explain how events occur from certain causes1010. Rothman KJ. Causes. Am J Epidemiol. 1976;104(6):587-92.,2424. Krieger N. Epidemiology and the web of causation: Has anyone seen the spider? Soc Sci Med. 1994;39(7):887-903.. None of the pharmacoepidemiology books surveyed mention any kind of causal model as a form of representation of the causal relationship,44. Bégaud B. Dictionary of pharmacopidemiology. Chichester: John Wiley & Sons; 2000. 171p.,1515. Laporte JR, Tognoni G. Principios de epidemiología del medicamento. 2ª ed. Barcelona: Masson; 1993. 280p.,1616. Carvajal García-Pando A. Farmacoepidemiología. Valladolid: Secretariado de Publicaciones, Universida, D.L.; 1993. 162p.,1717. Kennedy DL, Goldman SA, Lillie RB. Spontaneous reporting in the United States. In: Strom BL, editor. Pharmacoepidemiology. 3ª ed. New York: John Willy & Sons; 2000. p. 151-74.,1818. Yang Y, West-Strum D. Compreendendo a farmacoepidemiologia. Porto Alegre: AMGH; 2013. 198p.,1919. Coelho HLL, Santos DB. Farmacoepidemiologia. In: Almeida Filho N, Barreto ML, Eds. Epidemiologia & Saúde - Fundamentos, métodos e aplicações. Rio de Janeiro: Guanabara Koogan; 2011. p. 670-7., although most of these references cite the expression “multifactorial causality” 44. Bégaud B. Dictionary of pharmacopidemiology. Chichester: John Wiley & Sons; 2000. 171p.,1515. Laporte JR, Tognoni G. Principios de epidemiología del medicamento. 2ª ed. Barcelona: Masson; 1993. 280p.,1616. Carvajal García-Pando A. Farmacoepidemiología. Valladolid: Secretariado de Publicaciones, Universida, D.L.; 1993. 162p.,1717. Kennedy DL, Goldman SA, Lillie RB. Spontaneous reporting in the United States. In: Strom BL, editor. Pharmacoepidemiology. 3ª ed. New York: John Willy & Sons; 2000. p. 151-74.,1818. Yang Y, West-Strum D. Compreendendo a farmacoepidemiologia. Porto Alegre: AMGH; 2013. 198p..

The years 1957 and 1960 showed the first mention of multi causality models (“causation web”) in the epidemiological literature2424. Krieger N. Epidemiology and the web of causation: Has anyone seen the spider? Soc Sci Med. 1994;39(7):887-903.. According to Krieger2424. Krieger N. Epidemiology and the web of causation: Has anyone seen the spider? Soc Sci Med. 1994;39(7):887-903., this model was not designed to provide explanations for causal relationships, but to increase the capacity of epidemiologists to describe and study the complex interrelationships between risk factors and diseases. Based on his work, important inferences about prevention and research have been made, and they remain to this day as part of epidemiological thinking: “to carry out preventive measures, it is not necessary to understand causal mechanisms in their totality” and “even the knowledge of a small component may allow some degree of prevention”2424. Krieger N. Epidemiology and the web of causation: Has anyone seen the spider? Soc Sci Med. 1994;39(7):887-903..

In an article published in 1976, Rothman proposed a conceptual model of multi-causality called component-sufficient causes. It illustrates several relevant principles about causes. Perhaps most importantly, it shows that a given disease can be motivated by more than one causal mechanism and that each involves the joint action of various causes1010. Rothman KJ. Causes. Am J Epidemiol. 1976;104(6):587-92.. In this model, the causal agent may be composed of a constellation of causes (three or more, for example) that are also considered to be sufficient for the occurrence of an adverse event. That which makes up a sufficient cause is called a component, and there may be a minimum number of components necessary for an adverse event to occur1010. Rothman KJ. Causes. Am J Epidemiol. 1976;104(6):587-92.. In the composition of a constellation of causes, there is almost always a genetic and environmental origin1010. Rothman KJ. Causes. Am J Epidemiol. 1976;104(6):587-92.,2525. Rothman KJ, Greenland S. Causation and causal inference in epidemiology. Am J Public Health. 2005;95(Suppl.1):S144-50..

In suspected ADE, the drug is referred to as a component cause, even though other causes are needed. For example, there are people who, by virtue of their genetic makeup or environmental experience, are susceptible to anaphylactic reactions caused by medications, while others are not. These susceptibility factors are component causes of complete causal mechanisms through which the drug causes this type of reaction. A complete causal mechanism forms a sufficient cause, and there may or may not be a sharing of common component causes between different complete causal mechanisms1010. Rothman KJ. Causes. Am J Epidemiol. 1976;104(6):587-92.,2525. Rothman KJ, Greenland S. Causation and causal inference in epidemiology. Am J Public Health. 2005;95(Suppl.1):S144-50..

Rothman’s multicausal model further postulates that several causal components act together to produce an effect. This does not necessarily imply that component causes must act at the same time1010. Rothman KJ. Causes. Am J Epidemiol. 1976;104(6):587-92.. Patients’ hypersensitivity reactions to drugs justify this assertion, because during the patient’s first contact with a drug, this type of adverse reaction does not usually manifest itself, but rather what occurs is the production of antibodies that will be a component cause for the manifestation of the side effect in the patient’s second exposure to the same drug or to another drug that is part of a similar therapeutic class. This whole process occurs at different time intervals.

Drug intoxication, a type of ADE, can be seen in Rothman’s multi-causal model as the result of a number of different sufficient causes, each of which presents distinct doses of the drug as a component cause. Smaller doses probably require a more complex set of component causes for intoxication to occur, when compared to exposure in higher doses. It should be remembered that dosage is directly related to increase of risk and inversely to time, and alterations in the composition of these variables give rise to different intensities of the effect of the drug with regard to intoxication. In addition, the individual’s susceptibility is a component cause to be considered in the manifestation of this type of adverse event, although it seems probable that there are similarities in the components of sufficient causes of different individuals1010. Rothman KJ. Causes. Am J Epidemiol. 1976;104(6):587-92..

According to Rothman and Greenland2525. Rothman KJ, Greenland S. Causation and causal inference in epidemiology. Am J Public Health. 2005;95(Suppl.1):S144-50., it can be assumed that no cause is self-sufficient to result in the occurrence of an injury. In order to explain why an adverse event, such as Reye’s syndrome, occurred in a patient who ingested acetylsalicylic acid, other components of a complex causal model can be identified, such as underlying disease, the patient’s age, genetic predisposition, and nutritional state. In this case, such a model, which may involve different causal mechanisms, was sufficient for the onset of this syndrome2222. Vineis P. Causality in epidemiology. Soz-Präventivmed. 2003;48:80-7..

In practice, surveillance and control of causative components of a causal model that was designed in response to an injury can be understood in terms of time and geographic space. This argument corroborates the existence of a different type of decision-making, which saves time (or not) when adopting corrective actions, as well as increases sanitary authorities’ perception of risk in countries facing an imminent risk to society. An example of this was the delay (time) by health authorities in Brazil and other countries (geographical area) in the prohibition of the use of thalidomide for nausea in pregnancy, which resulted in a greater number of children born with congenital malformations2626. Paumgartten FJR, Souza NR. Clinical use and control of the dispensing of thalidomide in Brasilia-Federal District, Brazil, from 2001 to 2012. Ciên Saúde Colet. 2013;18(11):3401-8.. In this public health tragedy, a key component that allowed for the continuation of the phocomelia outbreak was the delay in defining sanitary legislation, which would prohibit or restrict the indication of the use of this drug.

DETERMINING A CAUSAL RELATIONSHIP

Establishing causal inferences between medications and adverse events is a complex and difficult process1515. Laporte JR, Tognoni G. Principios de epidemiología del medicamento. 2ª ed. Barcelona: Masson; 1993. 280p.,2727. Po ALW, Kendall MJ. Causality assessment of adverse effects: when is re-challenge ethically acceptable? Lancet. 1999;354(9179):683.. It is worth noting that causal models in pharmacoepidemiology and pharmacovigilance do not always refer to the typology of causes and their meanings mentioned above. In some situations, causality may be direct and the cause and effect can be easily perceived and defined. Fire is a direct cause of a burn55. Edwards IR. Considerations on causality in pharmacovigilance. Int J Risk Saf Med. 2012;24:41-54.. In other circumstances, establishing a causal relationship is quite challenging. For example, it took 20 years to associate the use of aspirin with the increased incidence of gastric ulcer bleeding,2828. Gharaibeh MN, Greenberg HE, Waldman SA. Adverse Drug Reactions: A Review. Drug Inf J. 1998;32:323-38. and it is even more difficult and complex to identify and associate the cause with the effect in chronic drug intoxications2929. Sipes I, Dart R, Fischer L. Toxicologia. In: Minneman K, Wecker L, Larner J, Brody T, Eds. Farmacalogia humana: da molecular à clínica. 4ª ed. Rio de Janeiro: Elsevier; 2006.. One of the difficulties in determining a causal relationship is the presence of alternative explanations, biases (systematic errors) and confounding factors.

Faced with complexity, technical-scientific thinking about the causality of ADE has evolved in two broad areas of public health: pharmacoepidemiology and pharmacovigilance3030. Jones J. Determining causation from case reports. In: Strom BL, editor. Pharmacoepidemiology. 3ª ed. Chichester: John Wiley & Sons; 2000. p. 525-38.. This evolution is demonstrated through the prominent mention of alternative explanations for the determination of causality in textbooks on pharmacoepidemiology44. Bégaud B. Dictionary of pharmacopidemiology. Chichester: John Wiley & Sons; 2000. 171p.,1515. Laporte JR, Tognoni G. Principios de epidemiología del medicamento. 2ª ed. Barcelona: Masson; 1993. 280p.,1616. Carvajal García-Pando A. Farmacoepidemiología. Valladolid: Secretariado de Publicaciones, Universida, D.L.; 1993. 162p.,1717. Kennedy DL, Goldman SA, Lillie RB. Spontaneous reporting in the United States. In: Strom BL, editor. Pharmacoepidemiology. 3ª ed. New York: John Willy & Sons; 2000. p. 151-74.,1818. Yang Y, West-Strum D. Compreendendo a farmacoepidemiologia. Porto Alegre: AMGH; 2013. 198p.. Strom, for example, devotes a chapter exclusively to bias and confusion in this science,1717. Kennedy DL, Goldman SA, Lillie RB. Spontaneous reporting in the United States. In: Strom BL, editor. Pharmacoepidemiology. 3ª ed. New York: John Willy & Sons; 2000. p. 151-74. while Yang and West-Strum cite Sir Austin Bradford Hill’s causal aspects for its determination1818. Yang Y, West-Strum D. Compreendendo a farmacoepidemiologia. Porto Alegre: AMGH; 2013. 198p..

Pharmacoepidemiology is a branch of epidemiology that includes the use of epidemiological concepts and methods in studies looking at the uses and effects of drugs in large populations3131. Shakir S, Layton D. Causal association in pharmacovigilance and pharmacoepidemiology thoughts on the application of the austin Bradford-Hill Criteria. Drug Saf. 2002;25(6):467-71.. The first mention of this science in the scientific literature occurred in the early 1980s.3232. Czeizel AE. The role of pharmacoepidemiology in pharmacovigilance: Rational drug use in pregnancy. Pharmacoepidemiol Drug Saf. 1999;8(Suppl. 1):S55-61. The American academic view encompasses pharmacovigilance and epidemiological studies, that is, it is not restricted to drug safety alone3232. Czeizel AE. The role of pharmacoepidemiology in pharmacovigilance: Rational drug use in pregnancy. Pharmacoepidemiol Drug Saf. 1999;8(Suppl. 1):S55-61..

Much of the consistent evidence regarding the causal relationship of drug-adverse events comes from pharmacoepidemiological studies3333. Howland R. Understanding and assessing adverse drug reactions. J Psychosoc Nurs Ment Heal Serv. 2011;49(10):13-5.,3434. Tozzi A, Asturias E, Balakrishnan M, Halsey N, Law B, Zuber P. Assessment of causality of individual adverse events following immunization (AEFI): a WHO tool for global use. Vaccine. 2013;31(44):5041-6.. Nevertheless, a study on its own, however well designed, is not enough to refute a causal relationship in an individual55. Edwards IR. Considerations on causality in pharmacovigilance. Int J Risk Saf Med. 2012;24:41-54.. Other relationships, including causal ones, are still possible, although unlikely, when they involve unexpected and unrecognized alternative explanations that may lead to an adverse event of a lesser incidence than the power of the study could demonstrate.

A constant challenge in pharmacovigilance - the science and activity related to the detection, evaluation, understanding and prevention of adverse reactions or any other possible problems related to drugs3535. World Health Organization. The Importance of Pharmacovigilance: Safety Monitoring of Medicinal Products' World Health Organization [internet]. 2002. [cited 2014 Nov. 28]. p. 1-48. Available from: http://whqlibdoc.who.int/hq/2002/a75646.pdf - is that complete data that allows for the evaluation of causality using different methods, such as the Naranjo algorithm used to establish cause-and-effect relationships, is not always available.55. Edwards IR. Considerations on causality in pharmacovigilance. Int J Risk Saf Med. 2012;24:41-54. And this is a critical aspect for pharmacovigilance systems2727. Po ALW, Kendall MJ. Causality assessment of adverse effects: when is re-challenge ethically acceptable? Lancet. 1999;354(9179):683.. Equally important is the presence of uncertainties regarding the nature of the evidence of causation, which arises from spontaneous reports of adverse events, characterized mainly by high underreporting. Another limitation concerns the binomial suspension-reintroduction of the drug — considered as a reference standard for the establishment of cause and effect relationships in pharmacovigilance — which is not very effective, for reasons of safety and ethics2727. Po ALW, Kendall MJ. Causality assessment of adverse effects: when is re-challenge ethically acceptable? Lancet. 1999;354(9179):683..

In order to bypass its limitations, health regulations in Europe have incorporated different methods that contribute to the surveillance and control of ADE, including epidemiological methods, such as observational studies3232. Czeizel AE. The role of pharmacoepidemiology in pharmacovigilance: Rational drug use in pregnancy. Pharmacoepidemiol Drug Saf. 1999;8(Suppl. 1):S55-61.. Unlike pharmacoepidemiology, pharmacovigilance is exclusively concerned with drug safety.

Although there are advantages to the inferential process of causality from prospective pharmacoepidemiological studies in comparison to retrospective ones, for both types of study, determining that a causal relationship exists requires a large number of exposed and non-exposed individuals that can be monitored for long periods of time55. Edwards IR. Considerations on causality in pharmacovigilance. Int J Risk Saf Med. 2012;24:41-54.. Thus, these studies are not the best option for short and medium term decision-making in public health emergency situations55. Edwards IR. Considerations on causality in pharmacovigilance. Int J Risk Saf Med. 2012;24:41-54., particularly in sanitary surveillance. Investigations in the field of pharmacoepidemiology may be useful with regard to this limitation3636. Mota DM. Investigação em farmacoepidemiologia de campo: uma proposta para as ações de farmacovigilância no Brasil. Rev Bras Epidemiol. 2011;14(4):565-79..

In addition to analytic studies, Hill’s3737. Hill A. The Environment and disease: association or causation? Proc R Soc Med. 1965;58(5):295-300. views, published in 1965, have been suggested as important aspects to be considered when inferring causality between exposure and outcome from noncommunicable diseases. They include: strength of association, consistency, specificity, temporality, biological gradient, plausibility, coherence, experimental evidence and analogy3737. Hill A. The Environment and disease: association or causation? Proc R Soc Med. 1965;58(5):295-300.. These points of view are presented and discussed in textbooks on pharmacoepidemiology44. Bégaud B. Dictionary of pharmacopidemiology. Chichester: John Wiley & Sons; 2000. 171p.,1515. Laporte JR, Tognoni G. Principios de epidemiología del medicamento. 2ª ed. Barcelona: Masson; 1993. 280p.,1616. Carvajal García-Pando A. Farmacoepidemiología. Valladolid: Secretariado de Publicaciones, Universida, D.L.; 1993. 162p.,1716. Carvajal García-Pando A. Farmacoepidemiología. Valladolid: Secretariado de Publicaciones, Universida, D.L.; 1993. 162p.. Hill’s aspects were important in order to affirm the counterfactual approach in the development of epidemiological studies, but they are still of little empirical weight3838. Ioannidis JPA. Exposure-wide epidemiology: revisiting Bradford Hill. Statist Med. 2016;35:1749-62..

Shakir and Layton3131. Shakir S, Layton D. Causal association in pharmacovigilance and pharmacoepidemiology thoughts on the application of the austin Bradford-Hill Criteria. Drug Saf. 2002;25(6):467-71. cite that Hill’s points of view can be applied when characterizing causality inferences in pharmacovigilance as long as the specificities of the available data, and factors such as underreporting, misclassification and poor quality of information are considered.

Any causal consideration based only on pharmacoepidemiological studies is not logically defensible and certainly not socially acceptable55. Edwards IR. Considerations on causality in pharmacovigilance. Int J Risk Saf Med. 2012;24:41-54.. To give an example, the safety signal has been convincingly initiated because of a series of spontaneous reports of cases of severe arrhythmias following the use of cisapride, including evidence following the re-introduction of the drug. No cardiac arrhythmia had been observed in these studies and the safety signal was not accepted until a causal mechanism was discovered — a prolongation of the QT interval — on the echocardiogram55. Edwards IR. Considerations on causality in pharmacovigilance. Int J Risk Saf Med. 2012;24:41-54.. This serious effect should have led to timely corrective actions, such as warnings about the risk of its use in patients prone to heart rhythm irregularities55. Edwards IR. Considerations on causality in pharmacovigilance. Int J Risk Saf Med. 2012;24:41-54..

Another important point in determining causality is the difference between association (correlation) and causality. A substantial part of the available scientific evidence in the literature is based on the association of variables, which are insufficient to demonstrate causality. The assumption that A causes B, simply because A is associated with B, is an error3939. Novella S. Evidence in Medicine: Correlation and Causation [internet]. 2009 [cited 2015 Feb. 19]. Available from: http://www.sciencebasedmedicine.org/evidence-in-medicine-correlation-and-causation/
http://www.sciencebasedmedicine.org/evid...
, and in ecological studies is called an ecological fallacy. However, sometimes a reverse fallacy occurs, and is represented by the discarding of certain associations, as if they were not sufficient to demonstrate causality3939. Novella S. Evidence in Medicine: Correlation and Causation [internet]. 2009 [cited 2015 Feb. 19]. Available from: http://www.sciencebasedmedicine.org/evidence-in-medicine-correlation-and-causation/
http://www.sciencebasedmedicine.org/evid...
. It is emphasized that a single association is not sufficient to reach a conclusion on causality, but multiple associations may conclude that A causes B, in conjunction with biological plausibility4040. Spiegelman D. Commentary: some remarks on the seminal 1904 paper of Charles Spearman "The proof and measurement of association between two things." Int J Epidemiol. 2010;39:1156-9..

In pharmacovigilance, when investigating an individual case of an adverse event, whose drug is considered suspect, the probability of having a causal relationship is not enough to ensure definitive conclusions. Lack of an experimental design limits the validity of causal inference in pharmacovigilance. This does not reduce the relevance of the research process in this science55. Edwards IR. Considerations on causality in pharmacovigilance. Int J Risk Saf Med. 2012;24:41-54.. An analysis of at least five aspects should be considered when determining causality in pharmacovigilance:

  1. temporal relationship;

  2. data on suspension-reintroduction of the drug;

  3. relationship between the event and the underlying disease;

  4. presence of a more probable cause;

  5. information on biological plausibility.

FINAL CONSIDERATIONS FROM THE HEALTH SURVEILLANCE PERSPECTIVE

One of the possible questions that can be asked in the area of health surveillance is how to use the knowledge about causality produced by pharmacoepidemiology and pharmacovigilance to avoid damage or improve population health by generating stable evidence. This is a complex task because certain observational studies in the literature have suggested causal relationships that were later refuted when tested in subsequent studies99. Broadbent A. Philosophy of Epidemiology. Johannesburg: Palgrave Macmillan; 2013. 228p..

Causality is of great practical relevance in sanitary surveillance in that it signals the need or at least the possibility for basing regulatory decisions that reduce exposure to damaging drugs or increase exposure when the drug is beneficial4141. Glass TA, Goodman SN, Hernán MA, Samet JM. Causal inference in public health. Annu Rev Public Health. 2013;34:61-75.. Decisions range from the inclusion of new warnings and label information to the drug being withdrawn from the market. This gradient of decisions implicitly and sometimes explicitly incorporates the recognition of the causal relationship, as well as considers the frequency and severity of the event in question. In other emergency situations in health surveillance, although the causal enigma has not been satisfactorily elucidated, decisions are made, including that of maintaining the status quo or making use of the precautionary principle4242. Vineis P. Scientific basis for the precautionary principle. Toxicol Appl Pharmacol. 2005;207:658-62.,4343. Tallacchini M. Before and beyond the precautionary principle: Epistemology of uncertainty in science and law. Toxicol Appl Pharmacol. 2005;207:645-51..

Despite recognizing that there are limitations on the causality evidence from pharmacoepidemiology and pharmacovigilance, it is still possible, in some contexts, to use them for health regulatory actions that promote and protect population health. The main challenge is to decide whether the knowledge generated about causality is reproducible and stable, that is, if a finding will not be quickly countered by subsequent scientific research99. Broadbent A. Philosophy of Epidemiology. Johannesburg: Palgrave Macmillan; 2013. 228p.. A practical way of experiencing this is to demonstrate that the causal relationship in question cannot be easily mistaken, given the best current scientific evidence available99. Broadbent A. Philosophy of Epidemiology. Johannesburg: Palgrave Macmillan; 2013. 228p..

As such, the role of pharmacovigilance systems is to identify results that have a good chance of being true and consistent. It should be pointed out that such results can be in clear opposition to strong economic interests, which are capable of generating new research often with a high risk of bias99. Broadbent A. Philosophy of Epidemiology. Johannesburg: Palgrave Macmillan; 2013. 228p.. Tobacco companies did this by funding a large amount of research that contradicted the claim that there was a causal relationship between smoking and certain diseases. However, the plausibility in the causal nexus proved sufficient to support the development of widely recognized policies that control tobacco smoking in several countries99. Broadbent A. Philosophy of Epidemiology. Johannesburg: Palgrave Macmillan; 2013. 228p..

However, many decisions in sanitary surveillance are not adopted merely by the scientific and technical evidence of causality. There is always an “extra” component in addition to the evidence. For example, the government may choose not to directly ban a drug because of civil liberties, and propose legislation that only restricts its use, 99. Broadbent A. Philosophy of Epidemiology. Johannesburg: Palgrave Macmillan; 2013. 228p. because evidence of causation alone can not tell whether a total ban on a drug corresponds to the most appropriate political measure.

An illustration of the “extra” component is the controversy surrounding the resolution of the Brazillian Health Regulatory Agency (Agência Nacional de Vigilância Sanitária -ANVISA), which in 2011 banned the marketing of three appetite suppressants and imposed restrictions on the sale of sibutramine in Brazil. The decision was based on causal evidence pointing to how the risks caused by the drugs outweigh the benefits in the treatment of obesity. After almost three years, the sanitary standard was repealed by Legislative Decree No. 273 on September 5, 2014. One of the justifications of the decree was that ANVISA’s resolution caused “great dissatisfaction among the medical profession, constituting a setback to the treatment of obese people in the country”4545. Brasil. Senado Federal do Brasil. Projeto de Decreto Legislativo nº 52, de 2014 - Original nº 1.123, de 2013. Brasil: Senado Federal do Brasil; 2013. p. 1-6..

Considering different scenarios arising from academic and regulatory debate, determining causality presupposes the integration of theoretical and methodological references, such as pharmacoepidemiology and pharmacovigilance. It continues to be matter of judgment, rarely based on only one study4646. Vandenbroucke JP. Can counterfactual theory be a complete theory of causality as we practice it in epidemiology? In: Centre for Statistical Methodology Seminar, London School of Hygiene & Tropical Medicine [internet]. 2012 [cited 2012 Jan. 23]. Available from: http://csm.lshtm.ac.uk/previous-events/seminars/
http://csm.lshtm.ac.uk/previous-events/s...
and it is fundamental in the evaluation of drug safety3030. Jones J. Determining causation from case reports. In: Strom BL, editor. Pharmacoepidemiology. 3ª ed. Chichester: John Wiley & Sons; 2000. p. 525-38.,4747. Meyboom RHB, Hekster YA, Egberts ACG, Gribnau FWJ, Edwards IR. Causal or casual? The role of causality assessment in pharmacovigilance. Drug Saf. 1997;17(6):374-89.. The adoption of these principles contributes to the improvement, the strengthening and the opportunity of sanitary surveillance actions with respect to the safety of the patient and the population. New analytical approaches using large data volumes, including data and text mining strategies and so-called “machine learning”, are already a reality in pharmacoepidemiology and pharmacovigilance, 4848. Salathé M. Digital Pharmacovigilance and Disease Surveillance: Combining Traditional and Big-Data Systems for Better Public Health. J Infectious Diseases. 2016;214(Suppl. 4):S399-403. and are requiring new and dynamic approaches in causality 4949. Antunes JLF. Um dicionário na dinâmica da epidemiologia. Rev Bras Epidemiol. 2016;19(1):219-23..

REFERÊNCIAS

  • 1
    Nebeker JR, Hurdle JF, Hoffman JM, Roth B, Weir CR, Samore MH. Developing a taxonomy for research in adverse drug events: potholes and signposts. J Am Med Informatics Assoc. 2002;9(6 Suppl. 1):S80-5.
  • 2
    Carrasco-Garrido P, de Andrés LA, Barrera VH, de Miguel GA, Jiménez-García R. Trends of adverse drug reactions related-hospitalizations in Spain (2001-2006). BMC Health Serv Res. BioMed Central. 2010;10(1):287.
  • 3
    Mota DM, Melo JRR, Freitas DRC De, Machado M. Perfil da mortalidade por intoxicação com medicamentos no Brasil, 1996-2005: retrato de uma década. Ciên Saúde Colet. 2012;17(1):61-70.
  • 4
    Bégaud B. Dictionary of pharmacopidemiology. Chichester: John Wiley & Sons; 2000. 171p.
  • 5
    Edwards IR. Considerations on causality in pharmacovigilance. Int J Risk Saf Med. 2012;24:41-54.
  • 6
    Bhopal R. Concepts of epidemiology: an integrated introduction to the ideas, theories, principles and methods of epidemiology. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2002. 639p.
  • 7
    Holland P. Statistics and causal inference. J Am Stat Assoc. 1986;81:945-60.
  • 8
    Parascandola M, Weed DL. Causation in epidemiology. J Epidemiol Community Health. 2001;55:905-12.
  • 9
    Broadbent A. Philosophy of Epidemiology. Johannesburg: Palgrave Macmillan; 2013. 228p.
  • 10
    Rothman KJ. Causes. Am J Epidemiol. 1976;104(6):587-92.
  • 11
    Hitchcock C. Probabilistic causation [internet]. 2012 [cited 2014 Dec. 13]. Available from: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/causation-probabilistic/#CauMarCon
    » http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/causation-probabilistic/#CauMarCon
  • 12
    Susser M. What is a cause and how do we know one - A Grammar of Causality. Am J Epidemiol. 1991;133(7):635-48.
  • 13
    Susser M. Glossary: causality in public health science. J Epidemiol Community Health. 2001;55:376-8.
  • 14
    Rothman KJ, Greenland S. Modern Epidemiology. 2ª ed. Philadelphia: Lippincott-Raven; 1998.
  • 15
    Laporte JR, Tognoni G. Principios de epidemiología del medicamento. 2ª ed. Barcelona: Masson; 1993. 280p.
  • 16
    Carvajal García-Pando A. Farmacoepidemiología. Valladolid: Secretariado de Publicaciones, Universida, D.L.; 1993. 162p.
  • 17
    Kennedy DL, Goldman SA, Lillie RB. Spontaneous reporting in the United States. In: Strom BL, editor. Pharmacoepidemiology. 3ª ed. New York: John Willy & Sons; 2000. p. 151-74.
  • 18
    Yang Y, West-Strum D. Compreendendo a farmacoepidemiologia. Porto Alegre: AMGH; 2013. 198p.
  • 19
    Coelho HLL, Santos DB. Farmacoepidemiologia. In: Almeida Filho N, Barreto ML, Eds. Epidemiologia & Saúde - Fundamentos, métodos e aplicações. Rio de Janeiro: Guanabara Koogan; 2011. p. 670-7.
  • 20
    Lagiou P, Adami HO, Trichopoulos D. Causality in cancer epidemiology. Eur J Epidemiol. 2005;20:565-74.
  • 21
    Organização Mundial da Saúde. Classificação Estatística Internacional de Doenças e Problemas Relacionados à Saúde. 10a ed. São Paulo: Editora da USP; 2012.
  • 22
    Vineis P. Causality in epidemiology. Soz-Präventivmed. 2003;48:80-7.
  • 23
    Aguiar T. Hempel: a teoria da explicação científica. In: Aguiar T. Causalidade e direção do tempo: Hume e o debate contemporâneo. Belo Horizonte: Editora UFMG; 2008. p. 177.
  • 24
    Krieger N. Epidemiology and the web of causation: Has anyone seen the spider? Soc Sci Med. 1994;39(7):887-903.
  • 25
    Rothman KJ, Greenland S. Causation and causal inference in epidemiology. Am J Public Health. 2005;95(Suppl.1):S144-50.
  • 26
    Paumgartten FJR, Souza NR. Clinical use and control of the dispensing of thalidomide in Brasilia-Federal District, Brazil, from 2001 to 2012. Ciên Saúde Colet. 2013;18(11):3401-8.
  • 27
    Po ALW, Kendall MJ. Causality assessment of adverse effects: when is re-challenge ethically acceptable? Lancet. 1999;354(9179):683.
  • 28
    Gharaibeh MN, Greenberg HE, Waldman SA. Adverse Drug Reactions: A Review. Drug Inf J. 1998;32:323-38.
  • 29
    Sipes I, Dart R, Fischer L. Toxicologia. In: Minneman K, Wecker L, Larner J, Brody T, Eds. Farmacalogia humana: da molecular à clínica. 4ª ed. Rio de Janeiro: Elsevier; 2006.
  • 30
    Jones J. Determining causation from case reports. In: Strom BL, editor. Pharmacoepidemiology. 3ª ed. Chichester: John Wiley & Sons; 2000. p. 525-38.
  • 31
    Shakir S, Layton D. Causal association in pharmacovigilance and pharmacoepidemiology thoughts on the application of the austin Bradford-Hill Criteria. Drug Saf. 2002;25(6):467-71.
  • 32
    Czeizel AE. The role of pharmacoepidemiology in pharmacovigilance: Rational drug use in pregnancy. Pharmacoepidemiol Drug Saf. 1999;8(Suppl. 1):S55-61.
  • 33
    Howland R. Understanding and assessing adverse drug reactions. J Psychosoc Nurs Ment Heal Serv. 2011;49(10):13-5.
  • 34
    Tozzi A, Asturias E, Balakrishnan M, Halsey N, Law B, Zuber P. Assessment of causality of individual adverse events following immunization (AEFI): a WHO tool for global use. Vaccine. 2013;31(44):5041-6.
  • 35
    World Health Organization. The Importance of Pharmacovigilance: Safety Monitoring of Medicinal Products' World Health Organization [internet]. 2002. [cited 2014 Nov. 28]. p. 1-48. Available from: http://whqlibdoc.who.int/hq/2002/a75646.pdf
  • 36
    Mota DM. Investigação em farmacoepidemiologia de campo: uma proposta para as ações de farmacovigilância no Brasil. Rev Bras Epidemiol. 2011;14(4):565-79.
  • 37
    Hill A. The Environment and disease: association or causation? Proc R Soc Med. 1965;58(5):295-300.
  • 38
    Ioannidis JPA. Exposure-wide epidemiology: revisiting Bradford Hill. Statist Med. 2016;35:1749-62.
  • 39
    Novella S. Evidence in Medicine: Correlation and Causation [internet]. 2009 [cited 2015 Feb. 19]. Available from: http://www.sciencebasedmedicine.org/evidence-in-medicine-correlation-and-causation/
    » http://www.sciencebasedmedicine.org/evidence-in-medicine-correlation-and-causation/
  • 40
    Spiegelman D. Commentary: some remarks on the seminal 1904 paper of Charles Spearman "The proof and measurement of association between two things." Int J Epidemiol. 2010;39:1156-9.
  • 41
    Glass TA, Goodman SN, Hernán MA, Samet JM. Causal inference in public health. Annu Rev Public Health. 2013;34:61-75.
  • 42
    Vineis P. Scientific basis for the precautionary principle. Toxicol Appl Pharmacol. 2005;207:658-62.
  • 43
    Tallacchini M. Before and beyond the precautionary principle: Epistemology of uncertainty in science and law. Toxicol Appl Pharmacol. 2005;207:645-51.
  • 44
    República Federativa do Brasil. Decreto Legislativo no 273, de 2014. Brasília: Congresso Nacional; 2014. p. 1.
  • 45
    Brasil. Senado Federal do Brasil. Projeto de Decreto Legislativo nº 52, de 2014 - Original nº 1.123, de 2013. Brasil: Senado Federal do Brasil; 2013. p. 1-6.
  • 46
    Vandenbroucke JP. Can counterfactual theory be a complete theory of causality as we practice it in epidemiology? In: Centre for Statistical Methodology Seminar, London School of Hygiene & Tropical Medicine [internet]. 2012 [cited 2012 Jan. 23]. Available from: http://csm.lshtm.ac.uk/previous-events/seminars/
    » http://csm.lshtm.ac.uk/previous-events/seminars/
  • 47
    Meyboom RHB, Hekster YA, Egberts ACG, Gribnau FWJ, Edwards IR. Causal or casual? The role of causality assessment in pharmacovigilance. Drug Saf. 1997;17(6):374-89.
  • 48
    Salathé M. Digital Pharmacovigilance and Disease Surveillance: Combining Traditional and Big-Data Systems for Better Public Health. J Infectious Diseases. 2016;214(Suppl. 4):S399-403.
  • 49
    Antunes JLF. Um dicionário na dinâmica da epidemiologia. Rev Bras Epidemiol. 2016;19(1):219-23.

Publication Dates

  • Publication in this collection
    Jul-Sep 2017

History

  • Received
    01 June 2016
  • Accepted
    18 May 2017
Associação Brasileira de Saúde Coletiva Av. Dr. Arnaldo, 715 - 2º andar - sl. 3 - Cerqueira César, 01246-904 São Paulo SP Brasil , Tel./FAX: +55 11 3085-5411 - São Paulo - SP - Brazil
E-mail: revbrepi@usp.br