Acessibilidade / Reportar erro

The Ontological Import of Adding Proper Classes

Abstract

In this article, we analyse the ontological import of adding classes to set theories. We assume that this increment is well represented by going from ZF system to NBG. We thus consider the standard techniques of reducing one system to the other. Novak proved that from a model of ZF we can build a model of NBG (and vice versa), while Shoenfield have shown that from a proof in NBG of a set-sentence we can generate a proof in ZF of the same formula. We argue that the first makes use of a too strong metatheory. Although meaningful, this symmetrical reduction does not equate the ontological content of the theories. The strong metatheory levels the two theories. Moreover, we will modernize Shoenfield’s proof, emphasizing its relation to Herbrand’s theorem and that it can only be seen as a partial type of reduction. In contrast with symmetrical reductions, we believe that asymmetrical relations are powerful tools for comparing ontological content. In virtue of this, we prove that there is no interpretation of NBG in ZF, while NBG trivially interprets ZF. This challenges the standard view that the two systems have the same ontological content.

Keywords:
Set theory; Class theory; Formal ontology

1. How can we compare the ontological content of different theories?

Within the context of a formal theory, an assertion is ontologically committing if it expresses a closure property of the intended models. For example, the power set and the union axioms express closure properties in set theories. If X and Y are elements in our set theory model, then the axioms guarantee that their union and ther power sets are also in the model. This property represents how an axiom generates ontological import. A detailed analysis of this conception leads to an understanding of existential aspects in formal theories (see 44 FREIRE, R. “On Existence in Set Theory” In: Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 53, 4, pp. 525-547, 2012.). But it is of no help if we want to compare different theories regarding ontology. We propose a different approach for this kind of comparison: If T 1 and T 2 are formal theories and T 2 can reduce T 1 but T 1 cannot reduce T 2 using a natural method of ontological reduction given in a metatheory, then the ontological content of T 2 is greater than that of T 1.

Now, what is a natural method of ontological reduction? We expect that if T 1 reduces T 2, then the consistency of T 1 can be proved from the consistency of T 2 in the corresponding metatheory. This and other related questions are dealt with in 11 FREIRE, A. R. Estudo Comparado do Comprometimento Ontológico das Teorias de Classes e Conjuntos, PhD thesis, Campinas, 2019., which is the source of the main results in this paper. Nevertheless, we will not be concerned with this question in its full generality here, as we will concentrate on methods of interpretations between first-order theories in a finitary metatheory. More precisely, using the method of interpretations and the above conception of ontological comparison, we prove that the ontological content of NBG is greater than the ontological content of ZF. This result goes against the received view according to which those theories are equivalent.

We will analyze the received view and point out its insufficiencies. It is based on the folklore conservativity result: NBG is conservative with respect to ZF. A detailed finitary proof of this result will be provided, as there is basically no modern proof for this in the literature. We will argue that the ontological reduction operating here is not conclusive, for the corresponding reduction method is partial. Hence, it is not clear if it gives a right transposition of the ontology. Also, it is always possible to strengthen the metatheory and weaken the reduction method in order to trivialize the comparison.

Therefore, for the equivalence claim, it is not enough to have one mutual comparison according to some reduction method in some metatheory. In the opposite direction, it is very significant to have an asymmetric comparison by a standard method of reduction, and this result will be proved subsequently, together with other related results. The absence of interpretation from NBG to ZF thus understood is a strong evidence for the thesis that the ontological content of the former surpasses that of the latter.

2. Novak’s model-theoretic reduction of NBG to ZF

From every model of ZF, a model of NBG can be obtained by the addition of definable proper classes. This construction has the important feature that the resulting model has the same sets as the original model. Therefore, the following reduction of NBG to ZF is obtained: Assume that α is a ZF-sentence and that NBGα. Let be a model of ZF, and let 𝒩 be the model of NBG obtained from by the addition of the definable proper classes. Since NBGα, it follows that 𝒩α. However, if 𝒩α, then Mα, for α is a ZF-sentence - it is about sets only - and and 𝒩 have the same sets. Now, the completeness theorem gives that ZFα, for is an arbitrary model of ZF.

The above reduction gives, in particular, a model-theoretic proof that if ZF is consistent, so is NBG. However, a bolder philosophical conclusion from this is that the ontological content of NBG is already present in ZF, as it can be easily fulfilled by the definable classes lurking in models of ZF. We claim that the bolder conclusion is unwarranted. The problem is that the metatheory in which the reduction takes place is too strong and the difference may be obliterated by its excessive strength. To make the point clear, assume that we were interested in comparing theories T 1 and T 2 in a metatheory which happens to be strong enough to prove the consistency of both theories. The equivalence between the consistency of T 1 and that of T 2 is, therefore, valid in such a metatheory, but no ontological comparison can be drawn.

From a proof of equiconsistency in some metatheory, one cannot conclude ontological equivalence. However, there is another reduction of NBG to ZF providing a finitary equiconsistency result due to Shoenfield. Although the above argument does not apply to Shoenfield’s reduction, which takes place in a finitary metatheory, we still claim that the bolder conclusion that the ontological content of NBG is already present in ZF is unwarranted. The problem is within the reduction method itself: It does not provide a reduction of the quantification over class variables, which gives NBG its extra ontological content, but rather just shows that the quantificational reasoning with class variables in NBG is dispensable and can be avoided in proofs of ZF-sentences. Therefore, there is no real reduction taking place here, there is no transposition of ontology, and the ontological equivalence does not follow. Shoenfield’s proof will be given in the next section and meticulously analyzed to support our claim.

3. Shoenfield’s finitary reduction

The finitary proof of equiconsistency between NBG and ZF was provided by Shoenfield in the article "A relative consistency proof" 99 SHOENFIELD, J.R. “A relative consistency proof” The Journal of Symbolic Logic 19, 4, pp. 21-28, 1954.. This article is written in the language of Principia Mathematica by Whitehead and Russell, and makes extensive use of the techniques developed in Grundlagen der Mathematik by Hilbert and Bernays. For this reason, we have developed this section by an excavation, a reverse engineering, in which the tools used were unraveled by the clues left in the article. In addition, changing the axiomatic system (see 77 MURAWSKI, R. and MICKIEWICZ, A. “John von Neumann and Hilbert’s School of Foundations of Mathematics” Studies in Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric, 2004.) poses several additional difficulties and, in many instances, the proof changes significantly.

We will expose here the technique used for the equiconsistency proof. Before doing that, however, we need to remember the finitary proof technique of Herbrand’s theorem. For this, we will go through the necessary definitions, then we will enunciate Hilbert-Ackermann’s theorem and, finally, the necessary part of the strategy for establishing Herbrand’s theorem.

Definition 1A formula α is open if all variables occurring in the formula are free.

Definition 2A theory T is open if all its axioms are open formulas.

Definition 3 α is a quasi-tautology if, and only if, α is tautological consequence of instances of identity and equality axioms.

Theorem 4(Hilbert-Ackermann) A open theory T is inconsistent if, and only if, there is a quasi-tautology α of the form¬β1¬β2¬βk, such that βiis an instance of some axiom in T for eachik.

The finitary proof of this theorem can be found in [55 SHOENFIELD, J.R. Mathematical logic. Addison-Westley Publ. Comp, 1967., p. 48 - 52]. It is important to bear in mind this theorem since it is equivalent to the existential case of Herbrand’s theorem.

Definition 5Let Q be a quantifier ∀ or ∃, then a prenex formula is of the form:

Q x 1 Q x 2 ... Q x n θ ,

being θ a open formula.

We call θ the matrix ofQx1Qx2...Qxnθ.

We can write the prenex form, without loss in generality, with explicit quantifiers ∀ e ∃, instead of using the Q. The general formula is of the form:

z 1 ¯ y 1 ¯ z k ¯ y k ¯ θ [ x ¯ , z 1 ¯ , y 1 ¯ , , z k ¯ , y k ¯ ] ,

being x¯ the sequence of free variables in the matrix θ. Using this notation will simplify the proof, since each quantifier ∀ and ∃ is treated differently.

Definition 6 A formula α is existential when α is a prenex formula of the form x 1 x 2 x n θ , being θ an open formula.

From prenex formulas, we have the following theorem:

Theorem 7 For any formula α, there is a α', such that:

  1. α' is a prenex formula;

  2. αα';

  3. α' is obtained by a primitive recursive procedure;

We call α' the prenex form of α.

Next we will expose Herbrand’s normal form. It can be understood as the representation of any formula by an existential formula through a procedure of elimination of universal quantifiers. Such elimination is due to the introduction of function symbols in language.

Definition 8 (Herbrand’s normal form) Let α be any formula, we build α H through the following procedure:

  1. α0is the prenex form of α;

  2. If α i is an existential formula, then α H is α i ;

  3. If α i if of the form x 1 x 2 x n y γ , we introduce a function symbol f, such that:

α i + 1 é x 1 x 2 x n γ y ( f ( x 1 , x 2 , , x n ) ) .

If α i is of the form ∀yγ, we introduce a constant symbol c, such that:

α i + 1 é γ y ( c ) ;

We can represent Herbrand’s normal form of a prenex formula

z 1 ¯ y 1 ¯ z k ¯ y k ¯ θ [ x ¯ , z 1 ¯ , y 1 ¯ , , z k ¯ , y k ¯ ] ,

for

z ¯ 1 z ¯ k θ [ x ¯ , z ¯ 1 , f 1 ( z ¯ 1 ) ¯ , , z ¯ k , f k ( z ¯ 1 , , z ¯ k ) ¯ ] .

.

Theorem 9(Herbrand) Let T be a theory without non logical axioms in the language. Then, for any prenex formula α in, it holds that:

T α in the language L there is a quasi-tautology β 1 β 2 β k , for which, for each i, β i is an instance of the matrix α H .

Proof. (Detailed strategy) The procedure for proving Herbrand’s theorem follows the steps:

  • 1. If α is an existential formula, the theorem is a corollary of Hilbert-Ackermann’s theorem:

  • We suppose that α is of the form x1x2xnβ, with β as an open formula. In this case, ¬α is logically equivalent to x1x2...xn¬β. Thus, T¬α¬β.

  • Because of that, Tα the theory {¬β} is inconsistent. By the Hilbert-Ackermann’s theorem, for {¬β} is a open theory,

  • β} is inconsistent ⇔ there is a quasi-tautology ¬(¬β1)¬(¬β2)¬(¬β1), with β i an instance of β for all i.

  • But this is equivalent to β1β2β1, finalizing the proof.

  • 2. We take, for the general case, a prenex formula α in the language ℒ

z 1 ¯ y 1 ¯ z k ¯ y k ¯ θ [ x ¯ , z 1 ¯ , y 1 ¯ , , z k ¯ , y k ¯ ] .

  • 3. Let ℒ be the language ℒ extended with functions used to built α H and T H the theory without logical axioms in the language ℒH , we should prove that:

T α T H α H .

  • 4. Since α H is an existential formula, we obtain a quasi-tautology for the extended language ℒH . Hence,

  • TαTHαH if, and only if,

  • there is a quasi-tautology with instances of α H:

  • For this reason, the proof of item 3 finish the proof.

  • 5. To prove item 3, we only show the strategy for the converse implication, that is, TαT'αH, since the direct proof is relatively simple.

  • 6. Let T c be the Henkin extension of T, defined in [55 SHOENFIELD, J.R. Mathematical logic. Addison-Westley Publ. Comp, 1967., p. 46], and T c+eq be the addition of equivalence axioms1 1 If c 1 and c 2 are special constant for the formulas ∃xα 1(x) and ∃xα 2(x), then the equivalence axiom for these constants is ∀x(α 1(x) ↔ α 2 (x) → c 1 = c 2. of Herbrand [55 SHOENFIELD, J.R. Mathematical logic. Addison-Westley Publ. Comp, 1967., p. 52] in T c , we show that:

  • (a) T c is a conservative extension of T.

  • (b) T c+eq is a conservative extension of T c

  • These two fact will be important to the following steps.

  • 7. We suppose that there is a quasi-tautology β1β2βq in ℒH , with β i being a instance of the matrix α H . We now do a procedure of replacement of functions introduced for α H by constants in ℒc . More specifically, if α H is of the form

θ [ x ¯ , z ¯ 1 , f 1 ( z ¯ 1 ) ¯ , , z ¯ k , f k ( z ¯ 1 , , z ¯ k ) ¯ ]

and β i if of the form

θ [ t ¯ , u ¯ 1 , f 1 ( u ¯ 1 ) ¯ , , u ¯ k , f k ( u ¯ 1 , , u ¯ k ) ¯ ] ,

  • we define the sequence of special constants d(u1¯)¯,d(u1¯,u2¯)¯,,d(u1¯,,uk¯)¯ for eliminating the functions in the following manner:

  • Notation 10 .

  • (a) z ¯ i is a sequence of terms of the sequence z ¯ from the index i onward;

  • (b) z ¯ i j is a sequence of terms of z ¯ from the index i up to the index j;

  • (c) ( z ¯ ) i is the i’th term in the sequence z ¯ ;

  • The constant (d(u1¯)¯)i is a special constant for the formula

( y 1 ¯ ) i ( ¬ y 1 ¯ ( i + 1 ) z 2 ¯ y 2 ¯ z k ¯ y k ¯ θ [ t ¯ , u ¯ 1 , d ( u 1 ¯ ) ¯ 1 ( i 1 ) , f 1 ( z 1 ) ¯ i , ] ) , (1)

  • begin * a abbreviation that indicates the remaining sequence

u ¯ 2 , f 2 ( u ¯ 1 ) ¯ , , u ¯ k , f k ( u ¯ 1 , , u ¯ k ) ¯ .

And, generally, (d(u1¯,u2¯,ui¯)¯)j is a special constant for the formula

( y i ¯ ) j ( ¬ y i ¯ ( j + i ) z i + 1 ¯ y i + 1 ¯ z k ¯ y k ¯ θ [ t ¯ , , d ( u 1 ¯ , , u i ¯ ) ¯ 1 ( j 1 ) , f 1 ( z i ) ¯ j , ] ) . (2)

  • By successively applying the substitution axiom and modus ponens, we have that, se βi' is the formula

θ [ t ¯ , u ¯ 1 , d 1 ( u ¯ 1 ) ¯ , , u ¯ k , d k ( u ¯ 1 , , u ¯ k ) ¯ ] ,

  • then Tc+eqβi'α.

  • 8. Note that variables can occur in u¯. However, to ensure the use of the equivalence axiom properties in T c+eq , we need all variables to be replaced by special constants. This will be necessary for the completion of the proof.

  • So we make a second transformation in the quasi-tautology. Here equivalence axioms play an important role: they ensure that any two equivalent formulas refer to a single constant 2 2 Realizing this characteristic was instrumental in establishing the relationship between the techniques used in (9) and the techniques presented in the book Grundlagen der Mathematik (10). In this paper, prior to his textbook of mathematical logic (5), Shoenfield makes use of epsilon Hilbert’s calculus as a way of guaranteeing the uniqueness of the special constants. Modern techniques make the conservative introduction of equivalence axioms. . With the addition of only the special axioms, we do not have this guarantee, since we could have two distinct elements satisfying the same formula of the form ∃.

  • We introduce distinct special constants for each variable in u¯, obtaining u¯'. Subsequently, we prove, using the special equivalence axioms, that

T c + e q u 1 ¯ = u 1 ¯ ' d ( u 1 ¯ ) ¯ = d ( u 1 ¯ ' ) ¯ T c + e q u 1 ¯ = u 1 ¯ ' u 2 ¯ = u 2 ¯ ' d ( u 1 ¯ , u 2 ¯ ) ¯ = d ( u 1 ¯ ' , u 2 ¯ ' ) ¯ T c + e q u 1 ¯ = u 1 ¯ ' u k ¯ = u k ¯ ' d ( u 1 ¯ , , u k ¯ ) ¯ = d ( u 1 ¯ ' , , u k ¯ ' ) ¯

  • 9. We use a similar procedure as in [55 SHOENFIELD, J.R. Mathematical logic. Addison-Westley Publ. Comp, 1967., p. 55] to obtain a formula β1"β2"βq", being βi" the replacement of the functions and variables introduced by the special constants shown above. Recall that the second transformation ensure us that Tc+eqβi"α by the same procedure as in item 7.

  • We suppose C 1 , C 2 , …, C m to be the proof sequence for the quasi-tautology that uses only identity and equality in T. Thus we prove that the transformation that have led β1β2βk to become β1"β2"βk" preserves tautologically the sequence. Therefore, β1"β2"βk" is tautological consequence of C1",C2",,Cm".

  • It remains to prove that each Ci" is a theorem of T c+eq , when C i is an axiom of T. This will result in the proof of β1"β2"βk" in T c+eq . Each C i is an axiom of identity, equality, an instance of identity or an instance of equality. We note that, when we get Ci", we have transformed C i into axioms of identity or equality, unless C i is an instance of identity. This last case, though, is easily proved in T c+eq from the propositions shown in the end of last item.

  • 10. As Tc+eqβ1"β2"βk" and Tc+eqβi"α for each i, then Tc+eqα.

  • 11.Since T c+eq is a conservative extension of the logic in ℒ, we lastly obtain that Tα.

3.1 Finitary proof of equiconsistency

In order to understand the finitary proof, it is important to consider procedures 7 and 8 of the previous section. In them, syntactic transformations are performed to provide the formulas βi", eliminating the functions introduced to obtain the Herbrand’s normal formula.

Each introduction of a function to eliminate a universal quantification is performed independently of the other introductions. In this sense, we can restrict the elimination procedure to certain universal quantifications. In fact, we can eliminate one, some or all functions introduced to obtain the Herbrand’s normal form.

For the proof of the equiconsistency theorem, we will use the direct part of Herbrand’s theorem to obtain the quasi-tautology. Subsequently, we will make the procedure of the converse proof of Herbrand’s theorem restricted to the variables limited to sets.

Before performing this procedure, we will eliminate all universal quantifications that are not restricted to sets in the NBG axioms. We will therefore prove that unrestricted universal quantifications are easily eliminated from the axiomatization presented.

Proposition 11 (Extensionality)

( z V ( z x z y ) x = y ) ( x y ( z ( z x z y ) x = y ) ) .

Proof. By substitution, we have

Σ = d e f x y ( z ( z x z y ) x = y ) { Σ } z ( z x z y ) x = y .

And, by generalization,

Π = d e f z ( z x z y ) x = y { Π } x y ( z ( z x z y ) x = y )

We should now prove that

Π ( z V ( z x z y ) x = y ) ,

We know that (αβ¬αβ)θ is tautologically equivalent to βθ. Thus, z(zxzy) x=y is tautologically equivalent to (zV(zxzy)zV(zxzy)) x =y. Nevertheless, since we know that, by definition, zVw(zw), then zV is equivalent to w(zw). From this, we have that zV(zxzy) is a tautology. We thus obtain:

z ( z x z y ) x = y

If, and only if,

( z V ( z x z y ) z V ( z x z y ) ) x = y

If, and only if,

z V ( z x z y ) x = y

Note that we can use a similar procedure to limit other quantifications to sets, whenever we have a universal quantifier ∀z for a formula in which zx occurs. Although this technique does not work in all cases, for the axiomatization of NBG used in this article the procedure is effective. We will not expose here the corresponding proof for each axiom, for they are all very similar. In this sense, we have the following theorem:

Theorem 12Let α be an axiom of NBG, then there is a formula α' such that α' is the elimination or restriction (to V) of all universal quantifications occurring in α andα'α.

We modify NBG yet one more time. The unrestricted existential quantifiers can be eliminated from instances of the scheme axiom for classes. We add, for each instance v¯Vzx(xz(xVα(x,v¯))), the constant c α and replace the axiom for v¯VxV(xcα(xVα(x,v¯))). Subsequently, we replace all other axiom of NBG by the version obtained by the successive application of the theorem 12. We call the resulting theory U.

We should prove the following theorem:

Theorem 13 For every formula γ, if N B G γ , then U γ .

Proof. In order to proof this theorem, we should just treat the case in which γ is the scheme axiom for classes. From this and from theorem 12, we obtain easily that U proves all other axioms of NBG.

We take a formula α with n free variables and in which all quantifications are bouded to V. We then prove that

U v ¯ V z x ( x z ( z V α ( x , v ¯ ) ) ) (3)

(We call this formula θ).

By replacement and generalization, we can eliminate the universal quantifications from the scheme axiom for classes. Thus we have Uθ if, and only if,

U ( v ¯ V ) z x ( x z ( x V α ( x , v ¯ ) ) ) . (4)

Since x and z do not occur in the left side of the implication, then Uθ if, and only if,

U z x ( ( v ¯ V ) ( x z ( x V α ( x , v ¯ ) ) ) ) . (5)

Let θ' be the formula

v ¯ V x V ( x c α ( x V α ( x , v ¯ ) ) ) .

We now eliminate the quantifiers of θ', obtaining

U x ( ( v ¯ V ) ( x c α ( x V α ( x , v ¯ ) ) ) ) .

Thus, by replacement and modus ponens,

U z x ( ( v ¯ V ) ( x z ( x V α ( x , v ¯ ) ) ) ) .

Therefore, Uθ. □

We continue by proving the lemma:

Lemma 14 Let α be a sentence without variables for classes.

If α is a theorem of U, then there is a proof of α in U that is free of unrestricted quantifications.

Proof.

By hypothesis, we have a proof of α in U. Let γ[x¯] be the conjunction of axioms used in the given proof, in which x¯ is the sequence of variables for classes that occur in the axioms. In this case, be the reduction theorem [55 SHOENFIELD, J.R. Mathematical logic. Addison-Westley Publ. Comp, 1967., p. 42]:

T x ¯ γ [ x ¯ ] α ,

or, equivalently,

Tx¯(γ[x¯]α), for x¯ does not occur in α,

in which T is the theory without non logical axioms in the language of U.

Let θ[x¯] be a prenex form of γ[x¯]α. The formula θ[x¯] is of the form

z 1 ¯ y 1 ¯ z k ¯ y k ¯ β [ x ¯ , z 1 ¯ , y 1 ¯ , , z k ¯ , y k ¯ ] .

From Herbrand’s theorem provability equivalence,

T x ¯ θ [ x ¯ ]

if, and only if,

T H x ¯ z ¯ 1 z ¯ k β [ x ¯ , z ¯ 1 , f 1 ( x ¯ , z ¯ 1 ) ¯ , , z ¯ k , f k ( x ¯ , z ¯ 1 , , z ¯ k ) ¯ ] ,

in which T H is the theory obtained by the addition of function symbols in T, according to Herbrand’s normal form x¯θ[x¯].

Let β' be a open formula

β [ x ¯ , z ¯ 1 , f 1 ( x ¯ , z ¯ 1 ) ¯ , , z ¯ k , f k ( x ¯ , z ¯ 1 , , z ¯ k ) ¯ ] .

By Herbrand’s theorem, there is a quasi-tautology β1'βm', in which each βi' is an instance of β' in the language of T H .

Let’s build the appropriate proof of α in U c+eq , obtained from U by the addition of special constants, special axioms and special axioms of equivalence.

From start, we replace each free variaable in β1'βm' for special constants. The result is a disjunction of m sentences that are quasi-tautological in U c+eq . This quasi-tautology is the starting point of the proof of α in U c+eq .

Subsequently, we replace the occurences of f1(a¯,b¯1)¯,,fk(a¯,b¯1,,b¯k)¯ for sequences of appropriate special constants. For this, we follow the items 7 and 8 in the proof of Herbrand’s theorem.

The result is the disjunction β1c1βmc', tautological consequence of instances of identity, equality, special axioms and special equivalence axioms, having quantifications only for the variablesz1¯,y1¯,,zk¯,yk¯.

Let θ ic be the formula

z 1 ¯ y 1 ¯ z k ¯ y k ¯ β [ t i ¯ , z 1 ¯ , y 1 ¯ , , z k ¯ , y k ¯ ] ,

obtained from β ic by the restating the quantifications z1¯y1¯zk¯yk¯. The closed terms in ti¯ are in U c+eq .

Each disjunction θ ic implies the corresponding βic' in U c+eq , as we have seen in the first paragraph of item 9 in Herbrand’s theorem proof. To show this, we use only simple properties of implication, of the quantifiers z1¯zk¯ and the special axioms used in the replacement of the occurrences f1(a¯,b¯1)¯,,fk(a¯,b¯1,,b¯k)¯ described above. From what we have exposed, it follows that

U c + e q θ 1 c θ m c ,

without using quantifications over classes.

However, since θ[x¯] is a prenex form of γ[x¯]α, we have

U c + e q θ [ x ¯ ] ( γ [ x ¯ ] α ) ,

using only variations of quantifications that occur in γ[x¯]α. Therefore, no quantification for class variables. On the other hand, by the rule of substitution,

U c + e q θ [ t i ¯ ] ( γ [ t i ¯ ] α ) .

As θ[ti¯]éθic, we conclude, using tautological consequence, that

U c + e q γ [ t 1 ¯ ] γ [ t m ¯ ] α ,

without using quantification for class variables.

On the other hand, γ[x¯] is the conjunction of axioms in U c+eq . Each γ[t1¯] can be proved in U c+eq using only tautological consequences and instances of the substitution rule. Therefore,

U c + e q α ,

without using quantification for class variables.

Finally, we observe that any proof of α of U in U c+eq can be transformed in a proof in U of the same α, and that this transformation introduces only quantifications directly related to the special axioms used [55 SHOENFIELD, J.R. Mathematical logic. Addison-Westley Publ. Comp, 1967., p. 52]. Since we haven’t used special axioms for class variables, the result follows.

From this result, we prove by finitary means the equiconsistency result:

Theorem 15 Let α be a sentence with all its quantifiers bounded to sets and such that N B G α . Then, Z F α .

Proof. Let α. be a sentence with all its quantifiers bounded to sets and such that NBGα. Thus, by lemma 14, there is a proof in U in which no unbounded quantifications occur. We call this proof sequence Seq.

We make transformations in this proof sequence that preserve tautological consequences, do not affect α. and such that the transformed axioms are theorems of ZF.

Let x 1 , x 2 ,...,x k be the free variables that occur in Seq. We add the following initial segment to the proof sequence x1V,x2V,,xkV, obtaining Seq*1.

Next, we apply the transformation *ZF in the formulas in Seq*1.

Every occurrence

  1. cθ=cα, are replaced by yV(ycθycα)

  2. cθx, are replaced by yV(y=cθyx)

  3. cθcα, are replaced by yV(y=cθycα)

  4. x=cα, are replaced by yV(yxycα)

  5. xcθ, are replaced by θ(x)

The successive application of this transformation to Seq*1 eliminate all occurrences of c θ , forming the sequence Seq*2.

Recall that, for each logical axiom Axiom in Seq*1, we should verify whether Axiomj*ZF is also a logical axiom or a consequence of ZF together with formulas x1V, x2V,, xkV. In the second case, we replace each axiom Axiomj*ZF in Seq*2 by the proof sequence of Axiomj*ZF. Hence, we obtain Seq*3.

We know the following proposition about functors [55 SHOENFIELD, J.R. Mathematical logic. Addison-Westley Publ. Comp, 1967., p. 30]:

Proposition 16 A functor * of formulas to formulas satisfies for every formula α and β:

  1. ( ¬ α ) * é ¬ α *

  2. ( α β ) * é α * β *

Thus, if δ is tautological consequence of γ1, γ2,…, γn, then δ*is tautological consequence ofγ1*,γ2*,,γn*.

Therefore, all transformations described above do not affect the proof tautologically. However, some instances of the logical axioms may not be logical axioms after the transformation. We now investigate what happen with logical axioms in which constants of U occur.

  • 1. Substitution axiom

  • There is no instance of the substitution θx(c)xθ in Seq*1 since unrestricted quantifications do not occur in the initial proof in U.

  • 2. Identity axiom

  • Note that (cα=cα)*ZF is yV(α(y)α(y)).

  • And this last one is a tautology.

  • 3.Equality axiom

  • (a) If the axiom is of the form x1=cαx2=y2x1x2cαy2, then, after the transformation:

( z V ( z x 1 α ( z ) ) x 2 = y 2 ) ( x 1 x 2 w V ( z V ( z w α ( z ) ) w y 2 ) )

  • We show that this formula is theorem of ZF and of the formulas x1V,x2V,,xkV.

  • If we have that zV(zx1α(z))x2=y2 and we suppose that x1 x2, the, by corollary 2 of the identity theorem in [55 SHOENFIELD, J.R. Mathematical logic. Addison-Westley Publ. Comp, 1967., p. 36], we obtain

z V ( z x 1 α ( z ) ) x 1 y 2 .

  • Then, by the substitution axiom in ex1V,

x 1 V ( z V ( z x 1 α ( z ) ) x 1 y 2 ) .

  • Using the variant theorem [55 SHOENFIELD, J.R. Mathematical logic. Addison-Westley Publ. Comp, 1967., p. 35],

w V ( z V ( z w α ( z ) ) w y 2 ) .

  • On the other hand, if we suppose that wV(zV(zwα(z))wy2), then, since zV(zx1α(z)) and by extensionality in ZF, we prove that wV(w=x1wy2). Hence, we obtain that x1 y2. As, from hypothesis, x2y2, we conclude that x1x2, finalizing the proof.

  • (b) x1=y1cα=y2x1cαy1y2. The strategy for item b is similar to item a.

  • (c) x1=y1cα=cβx1cαy1cβ. For this case, we obtain from the transformation:

x 1 = y 1 z V ( α ( z ) β ( z ) ) α ( x 1 ) β ( y 1 ) .

  • As x 1 and y 1 are free variables in the formula, the transformed formula is tautological consequence of x1Vx2V and instances of identity axioms.

  • (d) cβ=cαcγ=y2cβcγcαy2.

  • (e) cβ=cαx2=y2cβx2cαy2.

  • (f) cβ=cαcγ=cψcβcγcαcψ.

  • We prove items d, e and f by a simple combination of the strategies used in a and c.

Let’s now evaluate what occur to the aximos in U after the transformation *ZF:

The instances of extensionality, scheme for classes, replacement for classes and foundations are the only ones we affect by applying *ZF (only in those axioms constants of U occur).

  • 1. Extensionality. We evaluate two cases:

y V ( y x y c θ ) x = c θ . y V ( y c α y c θ ) c α = c θ .

  • After *ZF , we have respectively

y V ( y x θ ( x ) ) y V ( y x θ ( x ) ) y V ( α ( x ) θ ( x ) ) y V ( α ( x ) θ ( x ) ) .

  • Both are tautologies.

  • 2. Scheme for classes. Let v 1 , v 2 ,… v n be free variables occurring in θ

v 1 v 2 v n V y V ( y c θ θ ( y ) )

  • After *ZF , we have

v 1 v 2 v n V y V ( θ ( y ) θ ( y ) )

  • And this is a tautology.

  • 3. Replacement for classes.

x V ( f u n c ( c θ ) y V w ( w y v x ( ( v , w ) c θ ) ) )

  • becomes

x V ( v 1 v 2 v 3 V ( θ ( v 1 , v 2 ) θ ( v 1 , v 3 ) v 2 = v 3 ) y V w 1 ( w 1 y w 2 x ( θ ( w 2, w 1 ) ) ) )

  • Which is precisely the replacement axiom for ZF.

  • 4. Foundation.

( c θ 0 y V ( y c θ c θ y = 0 ) )

  • becomes

x V θ ( x ) y V ( θ ( y ) w ( w y ¬ θ ( w ) ) ) ;

  • We suppose xVθ(x). Then x(xVαθ(x)), for some ordinal a. Let A={x|xVαθ(x)}, it follows that ZFA0. By the axiom of foundation, y(yA Ay=0).

  • This is equivalent to

y ( θ ( y ) y V α w ¬ ( w y θ ( w ) w V α ) ) ( as w y w V α ) y ( θ ( y ) y V α w ¬ ( w y θ ( w ) ) )

  • That is, the formula is a theorem of ZF.

When axioms of U occur without constants, they can be understood as axioms of ZF, since we have added the formulas xiV.

  1. Extensionality yV(yx yz)x=z, since we have xV and zV, represents extensionality in ZF.

  2. The same is true for the axiom of replacement and foundation.

  3. The axiom scheme for classes do not occur without constants in U.

Therefore, in the sequence Seq *3, we have:

  1. formulas of the form xV,

  2. logical axioms,

  3. axioms of ZF,

  4. and all others are consequence of logical inferences from previous formulas in the sequence.

This is a proof in ZF. Since no transformation affect α, we have proved that ZFα.

Corollary 17 If there is α such that N B G α ¬ α , then there is a procedure that generate β such that Z F ¬ β .

Proof. If NBGα¬α, then NBG proves any formula. In particular, it proves a formula β¬β in which all quantifications are bounded to sets. Thus, by the theorem, ZFβ¬β. □

4 There is no interpretation of NBG in ZF

Before we prove there is no interpretation os NBG in ZF, we show some definitions as propositions:

Definition 18 Let V be a model of ZF and M a class V-definable, we say that the model M = ( M , V ) is a V-natural model.

Definition 19Let ℳ be a model in the languageZF (the only non logical symbol is membership) and an interpretationI=U,ϕofZF inZF (we writeI for ϕ (∈)), then we define the modelMI=(A,IM)emas

A = { x | M U ( x ) } and I M = { x , y | M U ( x ) U ( y ) x I y }

From this definition, we can easily prove by induction that:

Proposition 20Let ℳ be a model inZF andI=U,Ibe an interpretation ofZF inZF , then, for all sentences α

M α I M I α

The following proposition is a strengthening of a result in 1111 FREIRE, R. A. and TAUSK, D. V. “Inner models of set theory can’t satisfy V≠L” preprint, 2009.. They show that if the existence of a transitive model of ZF is consistent with ZF, then there cannot be a set-interpretation of ZF in ZF. Here, we replace that consistency condition for “ZF does not prove the inconsistent sentence for ZF itself”.

Proposition 21 Let I = U , I be an interpretation of ZF in ZF, if Z F { x | U ( x ) } is a set, then Z F ¬ C o n ( Z F ) .

Proof. Take I as in the proposition and suppose ZF{x|U(x)} is a set.

Let α be the Gödel number of the formula α represented in ZF. Since I is a set for every MZF, we define recursively the set T for each MZF:

Notation 22 a ¯ ( [ k ] = b ) is the replacement of the k’th element of the sequence ā for b.

  • α,a¯T if, and only if, a¯MI and

  • (1) if α if atomic of the form xixj,ai;aj(MI)

  • (2) if α is of the form βγ:β,a¯T and γ,a¯T

  • (3) if α is of the form ¬β:β,a¯T

  • (4) if α is of the form ¬xkβ:β,a¯([k]=b)T

  • for some bMI

By finite induction over the formula complexity, we prove that

Mφ,a¯T if, and only if, MIφ(a¯)

Take Pr ZF (x, y) to be the provability predicate for ZF defined in ZF and representing the statement “x is the number of the proof y”. Then, we say that Th(ZF)={y|xPrZF(x,y)}. Hence, since MIZF,MTh(ZF)T. As MI00, we have 00T. From this, we obtain M00Th(ZF). Once is arbitrary, by the completeness theorem, if ZF has a model, then ZF00Th(ZF). This is an absurd by Gödel’s incompleteness theorem. Thus, ZF¬Con(ZF).

Definition 23 Let V be a model of ZF and ℳ a V-natural model. We say that ℳ reflect a formula φ ( x ¯ ) if, and only if, for every a ¯ M

V φ ( a ¯ ) M φ ( a ¯ )

Theorem 24[Reflection theorem] [66 JECH, T. Set Theory Springer Science & Business Media, 2013., p. 168] Let V be a model of ZF e and ϕ1, ϕ2, …, ϕ n any sequence of formulas, then, there is an ordinal a such thatM=(Va,)reflect ϕ i for i between 1 and n.

We show that the desired result is a consequence of the reflection theorem and the fact that NBG is finitely axiomatizable:

Theorem 25 There is no interpretation of NBG in ZF.

Proof.

Suppose there is an interpretation I of NBG in ZF.

Since the number of axioms in NBG can be said to be finite, there is a formula α that is equivalent to the conjunction of all NBG’s axioms:

α is A x i o m 1 A x i o m 2 A x i o m n .

Thus, NBGα

and, from the interpretation theorem for first-order logic, ZFαI.

Suppose VZF, then VαI. By the reflection theorem, there is an ordinal a such that VααI. It follows that VaIα.

Since V α is a set, we obtain that the domain in VaI is also a set.

We define the model V* in ℒZF:

  1. The domain D in V* is such that D={x|VaIy(xy)}.

  2. The predicate V*={x,y|VaIxy}.

Since NBG proves the restriction to sets of all ZF axioms, we have that V*ZF. Since the domain VaI is a set, it follows that D is also a set. It means that ZFCon(ZF), absurd by the incompleteness theorem.

4 References

  • 1
    FREIRE, A. R. Estudo Comparado do Comprometimento Ontológico das Teorias de Classes e Conjuntos, PhD thesis, Campinas, 2019.
  • 2
    FREIRE, A. R. “On What Counts as a Translation”. In: Logica Yearbook, pp. 61-76 2018.
  • 3
    FREIRE, A.R. “Translation non Interpretable Theories”. Forthcoming in: South America Journal of Logic.
  • 4
    FREIRE, R. “On Existence in Set Theory” In: Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 53, 4, pp. 525-547, 2012.
  • 5
    SHOENFIELD, J.R. Mathematical logic. Addison-Westley Publ. Comp, 1967.
  • 6
    JECH, T. Set Theory Springer Science & Business Media, 2013.
  • 7
    MURAWSKI, R. and MICKIEWICZ, A. “John von Neumann and Hilbert’s School of Foundations of Mathematics” Studies in Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric, 2004.
  • 8
    NOVAK, I.L. “Models of consistency systems” Fundamenta Mathematica, pp. 87-110, 1950.
  • 9
    SHOENFIELD, J.R. “A relative consistency proof” The Journal of Symbolic Logic 19, 4, pp. 21-28, 1954.
  • 10
    HILBERT, D. and BERNAYS, P. Grundlagen der Mathematik. [Von] D. Hilbert Und P. Bernays, 1968
  • 11
    FREIRE, R. A. and TAUSK, D. V. “Inner models of set theory can’t satisfy V≠L” preprint, 2009.
  • 1
    If c 1 and c 2 are special constant for the formulas ∃ 1(x) and ∃ 2(x), then the equivalence axiom for these constants is ∀x(α 1(x) ↔ α 2 (x) → c 1 = c 2.
  • 2
    Realizing this characteristic was instrumental in establishing the relationship between the techniques used in (9) and the techniques presented in the book Grundlagen der Mathematik (10). In this paper, prior to his textbook of mathematical logic (5), Shoenfield makes use of epsilon Hilbert’s calculus as a way of guaranteeing the uniqueness of the special constants. Modern techniques make the conservative introduction of equivalence axioms.
  • 3
    Article Info: CDD: 511.3

Publication Dates

  • Publication in this collection
    12 Aug 2019
  • Date of issue
    Apr-Jun 2019

History

  • Received
    18 Jan 2019
  • Reviewed
    25 Jan 2019
  • Accepted
    02 Feb 2019
UNICAMP - Universidade Estadual de Campinas, Centro de Lógica, Epistemologia e História da Ciência Rua Sérgio Buarque de Holanda, 251, 13083-859 Campinas-SP, Tel: (55 19) 3521 6523, Fax: (55 19) 3289 3269 - Campinas - SP - Brazil
E-mail: publicacoes@cle.unicamp.br