Acessibilidade / Reportar erro

Critical analysis of the bioethics, work and health interface

Abstract

With the current Brazilian labor counter-reforms, the topic becomes more present in political discussions. In this context, bioethics can help to understand the limits and possibilities of the current social scenario. Thus, this study analyzes the interface between bioethics, healthcare and work, as well as its relevance as a research topic. We chose the reflexive essay format and divided the text into three parts. The first addresses the work in healthcare and its ethical aspects, the second presents the relation between bioethics and this type of work considering mainly its performance, and the third addresses the bioethical-work relationship through the criticism of morals and the laws in capitalism. Finally, we make a brief suggestion on how to base this topic from the point of view of expanding its scope from a critical perspective.

Bioethics; Work; Ethics; Civil rights; Comment

Resumo

Com as contrarreformas trabalhistas em curso no Brasil, o trabalho retoma sua centralidade. Nesse contexto, no que se refere ao setor de saúde, a bioética pode ser uma aliada para compreender limites e possibilidades do atual cenário social. Assim, este estudo analisa criticamente a interface entre bioética, saúde e trabalho, pensando sua atualidade como tema de pesquisa. Optou-se pelo formato ensaístico-reflexivo, com texto em três partes. A primeira trata do trabalho em saúde e de seus predicados éticos; a segunda apresenta mais diretamente a relação entre esse trabalho e a bioética, detendo-se sobre a questão do desempenho; e a terceira resgata a raiz da relação bioética-trabalho por meio da crítica à moral e à forma jurídica enraizadas no modo de produção capitalista. Por fim, lança-se brevíssima sugestão sobre como pautar este tema criticamente, de modo a ampliar seu escopo.

Bioética; Trabalho; Ética; Direitos civis; Comentário

Resumen

Con las contrarreformas laborales en marcha en Brasil, el trabajo retoma su centralidad. En ese contexto, en lo que se refiere al sector de salud, la bioética puede ser una aliada para comprender límites y posibilidades del actual escenario social. Así, este estudio analiza críticamente la interfaz bioética, salud y trabajo, pensando su actualidad como tema de investigación. Se optó por un formato ensayístico-reflexivo dividido en tres partes. La primera trata del trabajo en salud y sus predicados éticos; la segunda presenta más directamente la relación entre ese trabajo y la bioética, deteniéndose en la cuestión del desempeño; y la tercera rescata la raíz de la relación bioética-trabajo mediante una crítica a la moral y a la forma jurídica enraizadas en el modo de producción capitalista. Finalmente, se hace una brevísima sugerencia sobre cómo basar este tema para ampliar su alcance desde una perspectiva crítica.

Bioética; Trabajo; Ética; Derechos civiles; Comentario

Bioethics has been little requested in scientific research on problems regarding the work environment. However, with the labor counter-reform underway in Brazil, anchored in the neoliberal advance throughout the world11. Klagsbrunn VH. Uma leitura crítica dos conceitos de mundialização do capital e de regime de acumulação com predominância financeira. Crít Marx [Internet]. 2008 [acesso 9 maio 2019];(27):27-46. Disponível: https://bit.ly/2JrZesV
https://bit.ly/2JrZesV...
, labor becomes more present in health discussions. In this context, bioethics may help to understand some issues by discussing the social context.

In the history of capitalism and, more recently, neoliberalism, work is no more linked to human emancipation, being increasingly in the hands of super plunderers who do not hesitate to reinforce slave labor. Exploitation based on the deregulation of labor relations and successive threats to the workers’ right are only legal expressions of this social relationship. This issue can be addressed by bioethics, as long as this field assumes a philosophical position away from metaphysical speculations and exposes the materiality of the problem.

The labor world gathers a wide range of economic production activities. With the development of capitalism, the act of producing has changed profoundly, from advances in the service sector to the “intensive” technology sectors, used in all spheres of social relations, even in the most intangible ones. In this context, healthcare – a sector with a high level of intangibility – is not exempt from the changes required by productive restructuring22. Montaño C, Duriguetto ML. A (contra)reforma do estado no regime de acumulação flexível (pós-1973). In: Montaño C, Duriguetto ML. Estado, classe e movimento social. 3ª ed. São Paulo: Cortez; 2011. p. 180-224. , even in the public sector33. Grillo MGF. Direito processual e capitalismo. São Paulo: Outras Expressões; 2017. .

In health and other areas, whether in private or public sphere (but above all in the latter), legal relations tend to benefit management to the detriment of the worker, hampering the work itself and, therefore, undermining the right to health in its broad sense44. Scliar M. História do conceito de saúde. Physis [Internet]. 2007 [acesso 9 maio 2019];17(1):29-41. DOI: 10.1590/S0103-73312007000100003 . For this reason, a criticism of the legal norms – and, more deeply, the nature of Law – can lead to the roots of the problem.

Based on these premises, the aim of this article is to reflect on the healthcare work from the bioethics perspective, in a moment when flexibilization of labor rights is advancing in Brazil – an even more serious advance for the health sector, given the human cost of the process. For this purpose, we divided this reflective and interpretive essay into three sections: the first addresses the healthcare work and its ethical aspects; the second presents the bioethical approach, showing the plurality and challenges of discussions on the subject; and the third section focus on the roots of the relationship between bioethics and labor and on criticizing the moral and legal system founded in the capitalist mode of production.

Healthcare work and ethical aspects

The work-healthcare relationship is defined by the impact of economic interests on the human body. In this interface, a recurring question has prompted the discussion: to what extent is the imposed economic order ethically tolerable, in terms of resistance and adaptation of the human organism? In addition to the economic and biological perspective55. Berlinguer G. Medicina e politica. Bari: De Donato; 1973. , bioethics can be a fruitful field for a broad understanding of the possibilities and limits of such discussion.

There are many ways to understand work. However, regardless of the epistemological perspective, and especially in times of crisis in human relationships66. Cassirer E. Antropología filosófica: introducción a una filosofía de la cultura. Ciudad de México: Fondo de Cultura Económica del México; 1968. , it will always be the structuring factor of relations, no matter how much one tries to hide it. Here we rely on the understanding of healthcare work by Mendes-Gonçalves77. Mendes-Gonçalves RB. Práticas de saúde: processos de trabalho e necessidades. São Paulo: Cefor; 1992. , who considers it a process whose purpose is to meet the essential needs of populations. These would be basically the reduction of epidemiological indices, which to a large extent depends on the expanded understanding of healthcare, focused on social aspects, beyond the mere encounter between professional and patient.

In the public sector, the assessment of workers from a narrow perspective makes them victims of external intentions and managers who judge their work based on what they understand as a product. The result is a disregard of healthcare work teleology in its critical sense and the mechanization that turns individuals into consumers of doctors’ consultations. When healthcare work is considered in such limited terms, the ethical aspects of the bioethics-healthcare work interface become restricted to the sphere of morality, with the polarization between “good” (when the expected product is obtained) and “bad” (expected production fell short). For this reason, the ethical discussion must focus on the contemporary transformations of work, relativizing and facing the concepts of “harmony” and “social order” for coexistence88. Farias SF, Rocha JCS, Binotto MA, Schmitd KC, Borges GF. A ética no ambiente do profissional em educação física. Rev Bras Cineantropom Desempenho Hum [Internet]. 2006 [acesso 9 maio 2019];8(4):115-9. Disponível: https://bit.ly/39BkCXb
https://bit.ly/39BkCXb...
, 99. Azais SI. El descubrimiento del problema de la libertad en el proyecto filosófico de Kant. Stud Kantiana [Internet]. 2008 [acesso 9 maio 2019];6(6-7):193-206. Disponível: https://bit.ly/3dO5WqO
https://bit.ly/3dO5WqO...
in order to emphasize ideas of struggle, conflict, change and, of course, social overcoming.

Work can be both a social bond linked to liberation and achievement as a source of oppression and alienation of human beings1010. Cotrim G. Teoria do conhecimento. In: Cotrim G. Fundamentos de filosofia: história e grandes temas. 16ª ed. São Paulo: Saraiva; 2006. p. 54-61. . In the prevailing macroeconomic logic, which implies power relations1111. Heloani R. Assédio moral: a dignidade violada. Aletheia [Internet]. 2005 [acesso 1º abr 2020];(22):101-8. Disponível: https://bit.ly/2xDoNEA
https://bit.ly/2xDoNEA...
in the social division of labor and class cleavage, the exploitation and devaluation of labor assumes sophisticated forms, beyond the deregulation and loss of rights, under an idea of “flexibility” that undermines these bonds1212. Braga R. A política do precariado: do populismo à hegemonia lulista. São Paulo: Boitempo; 2012. . This devaluation of work weakens its moral function1313. Nardi HC. A propriedade social como suporte da existência: a crise do individualismo moderno e os modos de subjetivação contemporâneos. Psicol Soc [Internet]. 2003 [acesso 9 maio 2019];15(1):37-56. DOI: 10.1590/S0102-71822003000100004 and, to understand this from a bioethical perspective, we must go beyond deontology, emphasizing the current conditions of labor relations – disciplining, insecure and threatening – to which workers are subject.

The impossibility of dealing, individually or collectively, with situations that threaten positivist morality (produced/not produced) or questioning the purpose of this production generates moral suffering in the worker1414. Gomes D, Ramos FRS. Ethics and commitment of the health professional after the productive restructuring: a metropolitan area in Southern Brazil. Interface Comun Saúde Educ [Internet]. 2014 [acesso 9 maio 2019];18(49):289-300. DOI: 10.1590/1807-57622013.0647 and the degradation caused by working conditions. At this point, a tolerance pact is established with this type of violence (symbolic and material), silencing the collective and gradually weakening and destabilizing the worker, who little by little loses self-esteem and starts to doubt himself and even feels like a liar, since he is often discredited by his peers. Thus, his defenses are destroyed and his self-confidence broken, making it difficult or even preventing the exercise of a professional activity, in a situation that reflects on the family and social sphere1515. Bobroff MCC, Martins JT. Assédio moral, ética e sofrimento no trabalho. Rev. bioét. (Impr.) [Internet]. 2013 [acesso 9 maio 2019];21(2):251-8. DOI: 10.1590/S1983-80422013000200008 .

By its own nature, healthcare work is even more vulnerable to moral threats, since it occurs through living work in the act 1616. Merhy EE, Franco TB. Trabalho em saúde. Dicionário da educação profissional em saúde [Internet]. c2009 [acesso 29 jan 2020]. Não paginado. Disponível: https://bit.ly/3dI1had
https://bit.ly/3dI1had...
. However, such living work continuously deals with instruments, standards and equipment, with the interaction of different types of technology. These interactions shape the production of care, which should be based more on the subjective interaction between professional and user than on the mere application of protocols and rules1717. Deslandes SF. Humanização: revisitando o conceito a partir das contribuições da sociologia médica. In: Deslandes SF, organizadora. Humanização dos cuidados em saúde: conceitos, dilemas e práticas. Rio de Janeiro: Editora Fiocruz; 2006. p. 33-47.

18. Reynolds JM. Bioethics as care work. Hastings Cent Rep [Internet]. 2018 [acesso 27 mar 2020];48(1). DOI: 10.1002/hast.801
- 1919. Ambrósio EG, Lima VM, Traesel ES. Sofrimento ético e moral: uma interface com o contexto dos profissionais de enfermagem. Trab (En)Cena [Internet]. 2019 [acesso 27 mar 2020];4(1):258-82. DOI: 10.20873/2526-1487V4N1P258 .

All work is mediated by technologies and depends on their behavior. This relationship can be more or less creative, with focus on relationships or on logical processes of rigid instrumentation (such as machinery and equipment). In the medical work, for example, we can point out three elements that show the technological arsenal linked to professional performance: instruments (hard technologies), technical knowledge (hard-soft technologies) and intersubjective relationships (soft technologies). The physician can use and combine these three types to treat patients. Therefore, if the predominance of a more instrumental, less free logic is possible, the opposite can also occur if human relations become the focus in work relations.

Working conditions have an impact on the ethical problems experienced by workers, in a system of determinations so multiple that it makes it difficult to approach the topic with analytical precision. Therefore, we must keep the focus on the interactions in the natural social environment, with its laws and rules, always considering culture, customs and power relations. Moreover, the researcher cannot ignore the particular macroeconomic logic that determines these relations2020. Esposito R. Biopolítica y filosofía (entrevistado por Vanessa Lemm y Miguel Vatter). Rev Cienc Polít [Internet]. 2009 [acesso 9 maio 2019];29(1):133-41. DOI: 10.4067/S0718-090X2009000100007

21. Sass HM. La bioética: fundamentos filosóficos y aplicación. Bol Of Sanit Panam [Internet]. 1990 [acesso 9 maio 2019];108(5-6):391-8. Disponível: https://bit.ly/3dRlKJN
https://bit.ly/3dRlKJN...

22. Giancristofaro L. El hombre entero: bases antropológicas de la teoría del conocimiento en Dilthey. Thémata [Internet]. 2012 [acesso 9 maio 2019];(46):125-31. Disponível: https://bit.ly/2yl51Os
https://bit.ly/2yl51Os...
- 2323. Madrid NS. La función de la epigénesis en la antropología kantiana: las condiciones de ejecución de una “historia natural” del hombre. Thémata [Internet]. 2007 [acesso 1º abr 2020];(39):321-7. Disponível: https://bit.ly/2Jvr7jJ
https://bit.ly/2Jvr7jJ...
.

Bioethics and healthcare work: plurality and performance

Before starting the proposed reflection, based on Berlinguer, we should point out that in several countries not only the relationship between bioethics and work is not addressed, but older and inhuman types of exploitation persist, such as slavery and servitude, (…) practices (…) morally overcome for centuries and declared illegal since the 1926 Slavery Convention 2424. Berlinguer G. A relação entre saúde e trabalho do ponto de vista bioético. Saúde Soc [Internet]. 1993 [acesso 9 maio 2019];2(2):101-34. p. 105. DOI: 10.1590/S0104-12901993000200005 .

Regarding the work-bioethics interface, we turn to Lins, Vasconcellos and Palacios2525. Lins TA, Vasconcellos LCF, Palacios M. Bioética e saúde do trabalhador: uma interface. Rev. bioét. (Impr.) [Internet]. 2015 [acesso 9 maio 2019];23(2):293-303. DOI: 10.1590/1983-80422015232068 , who suggest this relationship is influenced by one of the most important milestones in the affirmation of citizenship: the Universal Declaration of Human Rights . Dated from 1948, the document defines work, in the article 23, § 1, as essential, explaining that everyone has the right to exercise and choose it freely, in fair and satisfactory conditions, being protected against unemployment2626. Organização das Nações Unidas. Declaração universal dos direitos humanos [Internet]. Paris: ONU; 1948 [acesso 27 ago 2019]. Disponível: https://bit.ly/3dLdY3V
https://bit.ly/3dLdY3V...
.

The reflection here presented starts from the crossing of two historical events, and considers that the correspondence between article 23 of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights 2626. Organização das Nações Unidas. Declaração universal dos direitos humanos [Internet]. Paris: ONU; 1948 [acesso 27 ago 2019]. Disponível: https://bit.ly/3dLdY3V
https://bit.ly/3dLdY3V...
and the four principles of Beauchamp and Childress’ theory2727. Beauchamp TL, Childress JF. Principles of biomedical ethics. 5ª ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2001. are not accidental. We can make the following association: everyone has the right to work and freely choose their profession (autonomy), the right to choose the field of action (justice), to have job satisfaction (beneficence) and, finally, to be protected against unemployment (no maleficence).

This analogy is essential for the discussion proposed, considering that, from a Marxist perspective2828. Marx K. Sobre a questão judaica. São Paulo: Boitempo; 2010. , one can question the liberal trend ethics of the very conception of “human rights”2929. Hunt L. A invenção dos direitos humanos: uma história. São Paulo: Companhia das Letras; 2009. . In the Universal Declaration , the worker seems to be within the scope of ideas, and not in the materiality of concrete life. Workers who are affected by pneumoconiosis, neurovegetative syndromes, silicosis and contamination by methylmercury or pesticides, did they “choose” their jobs? Whoever carries out activities with such risks certainly does not do so by free choice. The same can be said, for example, of domestic employment. Do young children dream of becoming a maid in the adult life? It is not about choice, but a question of lack of choice.

Regarding principialism, Schulte and Salamanca-Buentello3030. Schulte PA, Salamanca-Buentello F. Ethical and scientific issues of nanotechnology in the workplace. Ciênc Saúde Coletiva [Internet]. 2007 [acesso 9 maio 2019];12(5):1319-32. DOI: 10.1590/ S1413-81232007000500030 point out how work should follow the principles of autonomy, beneficence, non-maleficence, justice, privacy and respect. To this end, the authors report that employers must: 1) accurately present risks and dangers; 2) prevent them as much as possible; 3) communicate with workers; and 4) control risks so that employees can find them acceptable.

Under the same theoretical framework, Gattás, Segre and Wünsch Filho3131. Gattás GJF, Segre M, Wünsch Filho V. Genética, biologia molecular e ética: as relações trabalho e saúde. Ciênc Saúde Coletiva [Internet]. 2002 [acesso 9 maio 2019];7(1):159-67. DOI: 10.1590/S1413-81232002000100014 state that the discussion between bioethics and work traditionally highlights the conflict between rights, such as between the right to protection of employment and health, the right to information and privacy, or individual and collective rights. However, in practice, companies focus on the individual analysis of work, tending to make workers responsible for risky activities3232. Frank AL. Scientific and ethical aspects of human monitoring. Environ Health Perspect [Internet]. 1996 [acesso 9 maio 2019];104(supl 3):659-62. DOI: 10.1289/ehp.96104s3659
https://doi.org/10.1289/ehp.96104s3659...
.

An example: even when employees use appropriate personal protective equipment (PPE), the short time to produce expected by employers forces them to neglect precautions, since the attention needed is not compatible with agility. Even though the manager must provide PPE and the worker must use it (so that both are responsible for risk management), the responsibilities are uneven. In a critical perspective, if the worker relapses and maximizes risks, the ethical analysis must consider the demands of a hyper-accelerated production that, if not met, will lead the professional to unemployment. This is what is expected from a critical bioethical analysis on working conditions.

What we want to demonstrate is that Beauchamp and Childress’ principles, known to be liberal, are not enough to analyze the current work processes, especially in the “Global South” countries, knowing that the field epistemology has significantly changed in the last 15 years. Conservative market-paradigms, based on conceptions of freedom that reinforce the individualization of social subjects, reinforce the oppressive and unequal perspective of work. Thus, we emphasize here Latin American bioethics3333. Feitosa SF, Nascimento WF. A bioética de intervenção no contexto do pensamento latino- -americano contemporâneo. Rev. bioét. (Impr.) [Internet]. 2015 [acesso 27 mar 2020];23(2):277-84. DOI: 10.1590/1983-80422015232066 , which criticizes moral imperialism and coloniality (of knowledge, power and life itself).

In this field, we can mention Marxist authors such as Daniel Callahan3434. Callahan D. The roots of bioethics: health, progress, technology, death. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2012. and Martha Nussbaum3535. Nussbaum M. Not for profit: why democracy needs the humanities. Princeton: Princeton University Press; 2010. , in the United States, or Lucien Sève3636. Sève L. Para uma crítica da razão bioética. Lisboa: Instituto Piaget; 1997. , in France, or the Italian Giovanni Berlinguer3737. Berlinguer G. Bioética cotidiana. Brasília: Editora UnB; 2004. – a classic reference that we cannot forget in our analysis. In Brazil, we have publications focused on Latin American bioethics, especially intervention bioethics3838. Porto D, Garrafa V. A influência da Reforma Sanitária na construção das bioéticas brasileiras. Ciênc Saúde Coletiva [Internet]. 2011 [acesso 27 mar 2020];16(supl 1):719-29. DOI: 10.1590/S1413-81232011000700002
https://doi.org/10.1590/S1413-8123201100...
, which does not recognize the maximization of autonomy as a local principle, proposing notions such as “empowerment” or “liberation,” in the Freirian sense, indicating the workers’ power to combat the forces that devalue and oppress them. The Universal Declaration on Bioethics and Human Rights 3939. Organização das Nações Unidas para a Educação, a Ciência e a Cultura. Declaração universal sobre bioética e direitos humanos [Internet]. Paris: Unesco; 2005 [acesso 27 mar 2020]. Disponível: https://bit.ly/2Uy4H7G
https://bit.ly/2Uy4H7G...
can be a reference in this analysis, considering articles 3 to 17, especially article 14 that deals with social responsibility and health.

In summary, the relationship between bioethics and healthcare work focuses on subjective processes related to the nature of the craft itself, which can be summarized in three aspects. The first is work ethics as a normative code that ensures and disciplines the workforce; the second (associated with the first) refers to the social recognition of the worker as a citizen; and the third addresses the possibilities of ethics, as a reflexive practice, to rise up against and criticize hegemonic parameters, contrasting currents of thought that restrict or increase the freedom and decision-making power of workers1313. Nardi HC. A propriedade social como suporte da existência: a crise do individualismo moderno e os modos de subjetivação contemporâneos. Psicol Soc [Internet]. 2003 [acesso 9 maio 2019];15(1):37-56. DOI: 10.1590/S0102-71822003000100004 , 3030. Schulte PA, Salamanca-Buentello F. Ethical and scientific issues of nanotechnology in the workplace. Ciênc Saúde Coletiva [Internet]. 2007 [acesso 9 maio 2019];12(5):1319-32. DOI: 10.1590/ S1413-81232007000500030 .

An important contribution to the discussion in Brazil comes from the public health movement, which opposes the approach of the Economic-Industrial Complex in Health4040. Gadelha CAG. O complexo industrial da saúde e a necessidade de um enfoque dinâmico na economia da saúde. Ciênc Saúde Coletiva [Internet]. 2003 [acesso 9 maio 2019];8(2):521-35. DOI: 10.1590/S1413-81232003000200015 , and helps us to better understand issues related to the worker’s location, the incorporation of technologies and the construction of the Unified Health System (SUS). The movement has questioned the dominant health paradigms, opposing the market logic to the logic of social needs, with an ethical debate aimed at mobilizing professionals to rethink care.

In imposing an increasingly fast pace of work, for example, private interests overlap public interests. The market’s health parameters create an idea of human beings, civilization and life, which demand an ethics to think new technological advances and ways of working. In Latin America, this debate has focused on issues of social vulnerability, human rights, power and justice1414. Gomes D, Ramos FRS. Ethics and commitment of the health professional after the productive restructuring: a metropolitan area in Southern Brazil. Interface Comun Saúde Educ [Internet]. 2014 [acesso 9 maio 2019];18(49):289-300. DOI: 10.1590/1807-57622013.0647 .

Managerialism has been widely implemented in the public sector, and with this “performance” becomes an instrument of oppression of health workers. Work processes are increasingly subjected to productivism4141. Teston LM, Mendes Á, Carnut L, Junqueira V. Avaliação no SUS: uma crítica à ideologia do produtivismo no capitalismo contemporâneo. Saúde Debate [Internet]. 2018 [acesso 28 ago 2019];42(n esp 3):226-39. DOI: 10.1590/0103-11042018s317: the order is to produce more (and more thoughtlessly) in less time, even without the necessary technological input, as the focus of the performance logic is on the goals achieved and the financial incentives, not on working conditions.

The performance discourse preaches the idea of exceeding expectations and rewarding the employee who produces more than the established goal, classifying results from the perspective of meritocracy. However, such management paradigm considers only productivity and the amount of work4242. Barbosa L. Meritocracia à brasileira: o que é desempenho no Brasil? Rev Serv Público [Internet]. 1996 [acesso 9 maio 2019];120(3):58-102. DOI: 10.21874/rsp.v47i3.396 . Thus, although all work needs to be evaluated through a system that allows reviewing strategies and methods4343. Souza VL. Gestão do desempenho: julgamento ou diálogo. Rio de Janeiro: Editora FGV; 2002. , the logic of performance goes beyond ethical-moral limits.

This model, which goes beyond the absence of dialogue with unions and the intensification of exploitation4444. Remijo AP. A situação da classe trabalhadora no Brasil: sob o prisma de Rui Mauro Marini a superexploração do trabalho [Internet]. In: Anais do VIII Seminário de Saúde do Trabalhador e VI Seminário “O Trabalho em Debate”; 25-27 set 2012; Franca. Franca: Unesp; 2012 [acesso 9 maio 2019]. Disponível: https://bit.ly/2wVhEiP
https://bit.ly/2wVhEiP...
, generates moral problems by establishing a culture of unfair competition at work, with consequences for health care itself. Since 2011, when the performance measurement of teams and local health systems was legalized4545. Brasil. Ministério da Saúde. Portaria nº 2.488, de 21 de outubro de 2011. Aprova a Política Nacional de Atenção Básica, estabelecendo a revisão de diretrizes e normas para a organização da atenção básica, para a Estratégia Saúde da Família (ESF) e o Programa de Agentes Comunitários de Saúde (Pacs). Diário Oficial da União [Internet]. Brasília, 22 out 2011 [acesso 9 maio 2019]. Disponível: https://bit.ly/2wIN3Fn
https://bit.ly/2wIN3Fn...
, evaluations based on this logic have become the focus of management in public health services.

In the case of primary health care, such as the Family Health Strategy program, the teams, composed of at least one doctor, a nurse and a dentist, have specific processes for their assistance. However, several Brazilian cities use general performance measurement standards to assess these workers, disregarding the nature of their work.

For Junges and collaborators4646. Junges JR, Schaefer R, Nora CRD, Basso M, Silocchi C, Souza MC et al. Hermenêutica dos problemas éticos percebidos por profissionais da atenção primária. Rev. bioét. (Impr.) [Internet]. 2012 [acesso 9 maio 2019];20(1):97-105. Disponível: https://bit.ly/2UP3wjc
https://bit.ly/2UP3wjc...
, bioethics has already considered quite complex ethical problems in the hospital environment based on the traditional principles – autonomy, beneficence, non-maleficence and justice. However, they could not be used for primary health care, whose peculiar organization requires another type of analysis.

To investigate health work, we must see it in the light of the current performance evaluation paradigm, considering the ethical problems of this mode of production4747. Apellaniz A, Manzanaro R. Opinión de los estudiantes de carreras sanitarias sobre problemas éticos relacionados con las personas VIH+ en centros docentes, de trabajo y sanitarios. Arch Prev Riesgos Labor [Internet]. 2012 [acesso 9 maio 2019];15(1):13-9. Disponível: https://bit.ly/2WYzzzM
https://bit.ly/2WYzzzM...
. The discussion should always consider the risk that work may harm the lives of patients and health professionals, who suffer from stigmatization, prejudice and damage to self-esteem when trying to avoid the economic loss resulting from unemployment, and have their performance often evaluated by arbitrary parameters established by employers4848. Soskolne CL. Ethical, social, and legal issues surrounding studies of susceptible populations and individuals. Environ Health Perspect [Internet]. 1997 [acesso 9 maio 2019];105(supl 4):837-41. DOI: 10.1289/ehp.97105s4837
https://doi.org/10.1289/ehp.97105s4837...
. Thus, the debate must be deepened in order to build an applied, emancipatory ethics, based on reflective practice that respects differences and is open to otherness4949. Viveka D. Nursing ethics comes of age in India. Nurs Ethics [Internet]. 2014 [acesso 9 maio 2019];21(6):637-8. DOI: 10.1177/0969733014542557 .

The roots of bioethics-work interface

When addressing labor relations, the limits of liberal ethics5050. Fortes PAC. Reflexões sobre o princípio ético da justiça distributiva aplicado aos sistemas de saúde. In: Fortes PAC, Zoboli ELCP, organizadores. Bioética e saúde pública. São Paulo: Loyola; 2003. p. 35-47. become evident, since it emphasizes a supposed freedom without equality in the material reality. These systems reiterate the capitalist mode of production by treating it as inevitable and, by pretending to be autonomous, they reinforce a certain idealism5151. Bavaresco A. Idealismo realista ou realismo idealista: Hegel & Marx. Veritas [Internet]. 2018 [acesso 28 ago 2019];63(1):355-75. DOI: 10.15448/1984-6746.2018.1.29831 . However, if we recognize the importance of work in the constitution of the human being5252. Marx K, Engels F. A ideologia alemã. São Paulo: Boitempo; 2007. , we should admit that no form of idealism can be fully committed with the construction of a (bio)ethical thinking anchored in the empirical practice that could comprise working conditions in all its multiple expressions.

Ethical doctrines that aim at transforming and changing the world through ideas have limits, especially those based on liberalism. They are the deformed reflection of only one side of the real world, and precisely in the world where the relationship between people is subordinated to the law of value. In a critical Marxist perspective, bioethics is not dissociated from the emergence of sciences in general; it is not disconnected from culture and its forms. Therefore, the problem is not only theoretical, but essentially practical. After all, Marx understood that the reiterated discourse on “should be” did not include the comprehension of the “being” itself5353. Konder L. Ética marxista. In: Löwy M, organizador. O marxismo na América Latina: uma antologia de 1909 aos dias atuais. 4ª ed. São Paulo: Perseu Abramo; 2016. p. 585-90. . For this reason, Marxist ethics tries to face the profound changes in the conditions of existence – the impetuous development of science and technology, the contradictory phenomena of reality – redefining the values of real “human life”5454. Cano MCA. La bioética desde una óptica marxista. Educ Méd Super [Internet]. 2008 [acesso 26 dez 2017];22(3). Disponível: https://bit.ly/2UXmwfD
https://bit.ly/2UXmwfD...
.

Therefore, analyzing the relationship between (bio)ethics and work with principlist or even idealistic approaches could be too simple. The Marxist perspective of ethics would be more appropriate, defined by Barroco as a critical reflection and theoretical systematization guided by socio-historical assumptions and directed at emancipatory values 5555. Barroco MLS. Ética: fundamentos sócio-históricos. 3ª ed. São Paulo: Cortez; 2010. p. 84. . Therefore, we are aware of the ethics limits in a bourgeois society, but without denying that it can expand the critical social awareness that brings “being” and “should be” together.

With this, especially when discussing the bioethics-work relationship, we must view capitalism as a system with moral meaning. Although this feature is not exclusive to this mode of production, the fact is that, in this interface, capital becomes the center of criticism for not meeting the vital needs of the majority of humanity, proving itself incapable of providing material goods and social rights necessary for a dignified life to all individuals, which are enjoyed only by a privileged minority. On the contrary, capitalism keeps populations under subhuman conditions, denying basic rights such as food, housing, health, security, social protection and work5656. Vázquez AS. Ética. 37ª ed. Rio de Janeiro: Civilização Brasileira; 2017. .

As Ingo Elbe5757. Elbe I. Pachukanis versus Lênin: dois paradigmas da crítica marxista do Estado. Margem Esquerda [Internet]. 2018 [acesso 26 dez 2017];(30):25-34. Disponível: https://bit.ly/2UP9Kj4
https://bit.ly/2UP9Kj4...
points out, work has legal character only under specific historical conditions. An infinite network of legal relationships – like a web and, why not, a trap – emerges as a result of the gigantic collection of goods. This is how legal subjectivity (free, equal and fully capable personality) is built as a principle of the legalization of human relations in the capitalist mode of production. For this reason, Marxist ethical thinking must criticize the prevailing moral values and their fixation in laws and regulations, since they reflect and reinforce exploitation5858. Dias MCLC. O conceito de ética para Marx e Engels. Rev Dialectus [Internet]. 2016 [acesso 26 dez 2017];3(8):134-45. DOI: 10.30611/2016n8id5217 .

Valls5959. Valls Á. O que é ética. 9ª ed. São Paulo: Brasiliense; 1994. emphasizes that exploitation, especially today, takes on very subtle forms. Worldwide, it has assumed neo-colonial features, so that, in certain cases, bosses and workers from developed countries may share interests to the detriment of people in peripheral societies. Even in microeconomics, exploitation is no more seen as a policy but something supposedly organic, autonomous, intrinsic to a social order cleaved by classes in which the bourgeoisie (ruling class) uses the legal system for moral (and penal) coercion of those who sell their workforce.

In the established mode of production, human beings establish a relation to their work through commercialized products6060. Guedes É. A economia como sistema da representação em Karl Marx. São Leopoldo: Editora Unisinos; 2014. . They do so out of habit, ignoring moral explanations of how and why they live this way. As Pachukanis states, man as a moral subject, that is, as a person equal to all others, is nothing more than a condition of exchange based on the law of value. Man as a subject of law, i.e., as an owner of rights, also represents this same condition. Finally, both determinations are closely linked to a third, in which man appears as a selfish economic subject 6161. Pachukanis EB. Teoria geral do direito e marxismo. São Paulo: Boitempo; 2017. p. 153. .

It is in this sense that Pachukanis points out selfishness, freedom and the supreme value of the person as the three principles of legal subjectivity, demonstrating the responsibility of law in sustaining capitalist sociability. These principles are linked to each other and express the same social relationship. For the author, the selfish subject, subject of law and moral person are the three fundamental masks through which man acts in the society that produces goods. Economies of value relationships offer a key to understanding the legal and moral structure not in terms of the concrete content of the legal or moral norm, but in the sense of the legal and moral form itself. The idea of supreme value and equality between human beings has a long history 6262. Pachukanis EB. Op. cit. p. 154. .

The constitution of this Homo oeconomicus – with values coined in an supposed separation of economy from other elements of social life6363. Turatti MCM. Antropologia, economia e marxismo: uma visão crítica. São Paulo: Alameda; 2011. , acting under his own laws – brings about coercion, which aims to guarantee insignificant social behaviors, which reproduce capitalist sociability as a “natural right.” However, Marx and Engels5252. Marx K, Engels F. A ideologia alemã. São Paulo: Boitempo; 2007. had already made it clear that economics is the social production of life in all its relations – material, legal-political, religious, philosophical and scientific – composing an indivisible totality.

As Pachukanis asserts, if human thought, over the centuries, has so persistently turned to the thesis of equality among people and elaborated it in a thousand ways, then it is clear that some objective relationship must be hidden behind this thesis. There is no doubt that the concept of moral person or equal person is an ideological construction and, as such, does not fit the reality 6464. Pachukanis EB. Op. cit. p. 155. . However, until Marx, no one had questioned the historical reasons for this precept of natural law.

If the moral person is the subject of the capitalist production, then the moral law will be the rule of this society, which inevitably gives it an antinomic character. On the one hand, it must be social and, as such, place itself above the individual personality. On the other hand, the possessor of goods has freedom (of appropriation and alienation) and, therefore, the relationship with his peers must be present in each one’s soul, as an eternal law. Nevertheless, the Kantian categorical imperative6565. Goldim JR. O imperativo categórico. UFRGS [Internet]. 2003 [acesso 29 jan 2019]. Disponível: https://bit.ly/2R0l0rW
https://bit.ly/2R0l0rW...
brings together all these characteristics.

Despite the efforts of Kantians and Neokantians, Vázquez6666. Vázquez AS. Ética e marxismo. In: Boron AA, Amadeo J, González S, organizadores. A teoria marxista hoje: problemas e perspectivas [Internet]. Buenos Aires: Clacso; 2007 [acesso 29 jan 2019]. p. 316-27. Disponível: https://bit.ly/3aDejUj
https://bit.ly/3aDejUj...
recalls that there are particular morals, corresponding to each class, that coexist in the same society. For this reason, in the absence of real conditions for universal morality6565. Goldim JR. O imperativo categórico. UFRGS [Internet]. 2003 [acesso 29 jan 2019]. Disponível: https://bit.ly/2R0l0rW
https://bit.ly/2R0l0rW...
, one cannot speak of a system valid for all times and societies. Attempts like the Kantian imperative end up expressing particular interests in an apparently universal form.

Ethical universalism, which considers all beings as belonging to the same belief system, with one and the same “soul,” was imposed by the commercial expansion that has intensified the market flow with foreigners. People from different cultures, with different customs, habits and values, were “elevated” to the “abstract equality” of the autonomous morality of commercial society to mitigate the losses of the property owner. In other words, what is behind such universalism is the love for “one’s own (goods)” and contempt for “others.”

In a society of private class interests, freedom is supposedly universal. Private property, desired but not accessible to all, is explained in terms of “personal will,” “talent” and “individual efforts,” values that are crystallized in legal norms. And then morality can only be built under the aegis of greed. For this reason, social life, even in its most elementary forms, appears as a sphere standardized by norms, and labor products, which function as materials of these norms, are not simply objects of use, but use values 6767. Márkus G. Marxismo e antropologia: o conceito de essência humana na filosofia de Marx. São Paulo: Expressão Popular; 2015. . The human being becomes an “end in itself,” the other side of the selfish economic subject.

Bornheim6868. Bornheim G. O sujeito e a norma. In: Novaes A, organizador. Ética: vários autores. São Paulo: Companhia das Letras; 2007. p. 246-60. highlights autonomy as the first and most decisive (bio)ethical principle that accommodates the bourgeois type, representing the modern individual as the center of the social process. The big bona fide capitalist, for example, can ruin the small one without usurping his absolute value. The proletarian is “equal in principle” to the capitalist, a concept that finds its expression in the “free” employment contract. And it is from this “materialized freedom” that the worker can easily die of hunger.

The exchange, that is, the circulation of goods, presupposes that the participants recognize each other as owners. But how those who have nothing could be recognized as owners? Demonstrating how important their workforce is in the act of exchanging. However, the idea that the more qualified the worker, the better his conditions, has proved to be an illusion. The relationship between qualification and better wages – presupposed by the transformation of the workforce into merchandise – has clearly been deteriorating.

All this shows that equality of exchange is illusory6969. Cunha LLN, Dias MCLC. O significado das questões ético-morais para Marx. Saberes [Internet]. 2016 [acesso 29 jan 2019];1(13):35-48. Disponível: https://bit.ly/2X1PQnS
https://bit.ly/2X1PQnS...
, since the employment contract is based on the values of competition and performance, authorizing overexploitation. This is what expresses the categorical imperative, the ultimate representation of the ethical system of the commercial production society.

As Pachukanis proposes, moral conduct is opposed to legal conduct, which is characterized as such regardless of the reasons that generated it 7070. Pachukanis EB. Op. cit. p. 162. . In a very clear example, the debt will be paid because, in any case, the debtor was forced to pay it , or because the debtor feels morally obligated to do so 7070. Pachukanis EB. Op. cit. p. 162. . Thus, both morals and laws ratify the capitalist order; thus, external coercion (law), ideas (ethics) and their organization (system of norms) are fundamental aspects of the legal system.

Final considerations

Associated with the acceleration of work and the maximization of performance, the conflict between healthcare and work in the production of care is an ethical problem that tends to become more acute in our times. In this context, if bioethics does not engage in a critical shift regarding the capitalist mode of production and its legal form, it will lose the opportunity to improve emancipatory values.

When the legitimate objective of the State and corporations of increasing production clashes with the organization of work – especially in the area of health, which requires attention, calm, solidarity and humanization –, ethical issues emerge. At this moment, it is important to reflect critically, in order to point out solutions that avoid or reduce morally unacceptable risks, such as illness at work.

Investing in research on the relationship between bioethics and the labor world is important not only to create an area of convergence between knowledge, but also to fight injustices. We hope the proposals in this article will help those interested in forming a project agenda, fulfilling the objective of clarifying the aspects that such interface may take, in search of dialogue and solutions.

Referências

  • 1
    Klagsbrunn VH. Uma leitura crítica dos conceitos de mundialização do capital e de regime de acumulação com predominância financeira. Crít Marx [Internet]. 2008 [acesso 9 maio 2019];(27):27-46. Disponível: https://bit.ly/2JrZesV
    » https://bit.ly/2JrZesV
  • 2
    Montaño C, Duriguetto ML. A (contra)reforma do estado no regime de acumulação flexível (pós-1973). In: Montaño C, Duriguetto ML. Estado, classe e movimento social. 3ª ed. São Paulo: Cortez; 2011. p. 180-224.
  • 3
    Grillo MGF. Direito processual e capitalismo. São Paulo: Outras Expressões; 2017.
  • 4
    Scliar M. História do conceito de saúde. Physis [Internet]. 2007 [acesso 9 maio 2019];17(1):29-41. DOI: 10.1590/S0103-73312007000100003
  • 5
    Berlinguer G. Medicina e politica. Bari: De Donato; 1973.
  • 6
    Cassirer E. Antropología filosófica: introducción a una filosofía de la cultura. Ciudad de México: Fondo de Cultura Económica del México; 1968.
  • 7
    Mendes-Gonçalves RB. Práticas de saúde: processos de trabalho e necessidades. São Paulo: Cefor; 1992.
  • 8
    Farias SF, Rocha JCS, Binotto MA, Schmitd KC, Borges GF. A ética no ambiente do profissional em educação física. Rev Bras Cineantropom Desempenho Hum [Internet]. 2006 [acesso 9 maio 2019];8(4):115-9. Disponível: https://bit.ly/39BkCXb
    » https://bit.ly/39BkCXb
  • 9
    Azais SI. El descubrimiento del problema de la libertad en el proyecto filosófico de Kant. Stud Kantiana [Internet]. 2008 [acesso 9 maio 2019];6(6-7):193-206. Disponível: https://bit.ly/3dO5WqO
    » https://bit.ly/3dO5WqO
  • 10
    Cotrim G. Teoria do conhecimento. In: Cotrim G. Fundamentos de filosofia: história e grandes temas. 16ª ed. São Paulo: Saraiva; 2006. p. 54-61.
  • 11
    Heloani R. Assédio moral: a dignidade violada. Aletheia [Internet]. 2005 [acesso 1º abr 2020];(22):101-8. Disponível: https://bit.ly/2xDoNEA
    » https://bit.ly/2xDoNEA
  • 12
    Braga R. A política do precariado: do populismo à hegemonia lulista. São Paulo: Boitempo; 2012.
  • 13
    Nardi HC. A propriedade social como suporte da existência: a crise do individualismo moderno e os modos de subjetivação contemporâneos. Psicol Soc [Internet]. 2003 [acesso 9 maio 2019];15(1):37-56. DOI: 10.1590/S0102-71822003000100004
  • 14
    Gomes D, Ramos FRS. Ethics and commitment of the health professional after the productive restructuring: a metropolitan area in Southern Brazil. Interface Comun Saúde Educ [Internet]. 2014 [acesso 9 maio 2019];18(49):289-300. DOI: 10.1590/1807-57622013.0647
  • 15
    Bobroff MCC, Martins JT. Assédio moral, ética e sofrimento no trabalho. Rev. bioét. (Impr.) [Internet]. 2013 [acesso 9 maio 2019];21(2):251-8. DOI: 10.1590/S1983-80422013000200008
  • 16
    Merhy EE, Franco TB. Trabalho em saúde. Dicionário da educação profissional em saúde [Internet]. c2009 [acesso 29 jan 2020]. Não paginado. Disponível: https://bit.ly/3dI1had
    » https://bit.ly/3dI1had
  • 17
    Deslandes SF. Humanização: revisitando o conceito a partir das contribuições da sociologia médica. In: Deslandes SF, organizadora. Humanização dos cuidados em saúde: conceitos, dilemas e práticas. Rio de Janeiro: Editora Fiocruz; 2006. p. 33-47.
  • 18
    Reynolds JM. Bioethics as care work. Hastings Cent Rep [Internet]. 2018 [acesso 27 mar 2020];48(1). DOI: 10.1002/hast.801
  • 19
    Ambrósio EG, Lima VM, Traesel ES. Sofrimento ético e moral: uma interface com o contexto dos profissionais de enfermagem. Trab (En)Cena [Internet]. 2019 [acesso 27 mar 2020];4(1):258-82. DOI: 10.20873/2526-1487V4N1P258
  • 20
    Esposito R. Biopolítica y filosofía (entrevistado por Vanessa Lemm y Miguel Vatter). Rev Cienc Polít [Internet]. 2009 [acesso 9 maio 2019];29(1):133-41. DOI: 10.4067/S0718-090X2009000100007
  • 21
    Sass HM. La bioética: fundamentos filosóficos y aplicación. Bol Of Sanit Panam [Internet]. 1990 [acesso 9 maio 2019];108(5-6):391-8. Disponível: https://bit.ly/3dRlKJN
    » https://bit.ly/3dRlKJN
  • 22
    Giancristofaro L. El hombre entero: bases antropológicas de la teoría del conocimiento en Dilthey. Thémata [Internet]. 2012 [acesso 9 maio 2019];(46):125-31. Disponível: https://bit.ly/2yl51Os
    » https://bit.ly/2yl51Os
  • 23
    Madrid NS. La función de la epigénesis en la antropología kantiana: las condiciones de ejecución de una “historia natural” del hombre. Thémata [Internet]. 2007 [acesso 1º abr 2020];(39):321-7. Disponível: https://bit.ly/2Jvr7jJ
    » https://bit.ly/2Jvr7jJ
  • 24
    Berlinguer G. A relação entre saúde e trabalho do ponto de vista bioético. Saúde Soc [Internet]. 1993 [acesso 9 maio 2019];2(2):101-34. p. 105. DOI: 10.1590/S0104-12901993000200005
  • 25
    Lins TA, Vasconcellos LCF, Palacios M. Bioética e saúde do trabalhador: uma interface. Rev. bioét. (Impr.) [Internet]. 2015 [acesso 9 maio 2019];23(2):293-303. DOI: 10.1590/1983-80422015232068
  • 26
    Organização das Nações Unidas. Declaração universal dos direitos humanos [Internet]. Paris: ONU; 1948 [acesso 27 ago 2019]. Disponível: https://bit.ly/3dLdY3V
    » https://bit.ly/3dLdY3V
  • 27
    Beauchamp TL, Childress JF. Principles of biomedical ethics. 5ª ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2001.
  • 28
    Marx K. Sobre a questão judaica. São Paulo: Boitempo; 2010.
  • 29
    Hunt L. A invenção dos direitos humanos: uma história. São Paulo: Companhia das Letras; 2009.
  • 30
    Schulte PA, Salamanca-Buentello F. Ethical and scientific issues of nanotechnology in the workplace. Ciênc Saúde Coletiva [Internet]. 2007 [acesso 9 maio 2019];12(5):1319-32. DOI: 10.1590/ S1413-81232007000500030
  • 31
    Gattás GJF, Segre M, Wünsch Filho V. Genética, biologia molecular e ética: as relações trabalho e saúde. Ciênc Saúde Coletiva [Internet]. 2002 [acesso 9 maio 2019];7(1):159-67. DOI: 10.1590/S1413-81232002000100014
  • 32
    Frank AL. Scientific and ethical aspects of human monitoring. Environ Health Perspect [Internet]. 1996 [acesso 9 maio 2019];104(supl 3):659-62. DOI: 10.1289/ehp.96104s3659
    » https://doi.org/10.1289/ehp.96104s3659
  • 33
    Feitosa SF, Nascimento WF. A bioética de intervenção no contexto do pensamento latino- -americano contemporâneo. Rev. bioét. (Impr.) [Internet]. 2015 [acesso 27 mar 2020];23(2):277-84. DOI: 10.1590/1983-80422015232066
  • 34
    Callahan D. The roots of bioethics: health, progress, technology, death. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2012.
  • 35
    Nussbaum M. Not for profit: why democracy needs the humanities. Princeton: Princeton University Press; 2010.
  • 36
    Sève L. Para uma crítica da razão bioética. Lisboa: Instituto Piaget; 1997.
  • 37
    Berlinguer G. Bioética cotidiana. Brasília: Editora UnB; 2004.
  • 38
    Porto D, Garrafa V. A influência da Reforma Sanitária na construção das bioéticas brasileiras. Ciênc Saúde Coletiva [Internet]. 2011 [acesso 27 mar 2020];16(supl 1):719-29. DOI: 10.1590/S1413-81232011000700002
    » https://doi.org/10.1590/S1413-81232011000700002
  • 39
    Organização das Nações Unidas para a Educação, a Ciência e a Cultura. Declaração universal sobre bioética e direitos humanos [Internet]. Paris: Unesco; 2005 [acesso 27 mar 2020]. Disponível: https://bit.ly/2Uy4H7G
    » https://bit.ly/2Uy4H7G
  • 40
    Gadelha CAG. O complexo industrial da saúde e a necessidade de um enfoque dinâmico na economia da saúde. Ciênc Saúde Coletiva [Internet]. 2003 [acesso 9 maio 2019];8(2):521-35. DOI: 10.1590/S1413-81232003000200015
  • 41
    Teston LM, Mendes Á, Carnut L, Junqueira V. Avaliação no SUS: uma crítica à ideologia do produtivismo no capitalismo contemporâneo. Saúde Debate [Internet]. 2018 [acesso 28 ago 2019];42(n esp 3):226-39. DOI: 10.1590/0103-11042018s317
  • 42
    Barbosa L. Meritocracia à brasileira: o que é desempenho no Brasil? Rev Serv Público [Internet]. 1996 [acesso 9 maio 2019];120(3):58-102. DOI: 10.21874/rsp.v47i3.396
  • 43
    Souza VL. Gestão do desempenho: julgamento ou diálogo. Rio de Janeiro: Editora FGV; 2002.
  • 44
    Remijo AP. A situação da classe trabalhadora no Brasil: sob o prisma de Rui Mauro Marini a superexploração do trabalho [Internet]. In: Anais do VIII Seminário de Saúde do Trabalhador e VI Seminário “O Trabalho em Debate”; 25-27 set 2012; Franca. Franca: Unesp; 2012 [acesso 9 maio 2019]. Disponível: https://bit.ly/2wVhEiP
    » https://bit.ly/2wVhEiP
  • 45
    Brasil. Ministério da Saúde. Portaria nº 2.488, de 21 de outubro de 2011. Aprova a Política Nacional de Atenção Básica, estabelecendo a revisão de diretrizes e normas para a organização da atenção básica, para a Estratégia Saúde da Família (ESF) e o Programa de Agentes Comunitários de Saúde (Pacs). Diário Oficial da União [Internet]. Brasília, 22 out 2011 [acesso 9 maio 2019]. Disponível: https://bit.ly/2wIN3Fn
    » https://bit.ly/2wIN3Fn
  • 46
    Junges JR, Schaefer R, Nora CRD, Basso M, Silocchi C, Souza MC et al. Hermenêutica dos problemas éticos percebidos por profissionais da atenção primária. Rev. bioét. (Impr.) [Internet]. 2012 [acesso 9 maio 2019];20(1):97-105. Disponível: https://bit.ly/2UP3wjc
    » https://bit.ly/2UP3wjc
  • 47
    Apellaniz A, Manzanaro R. Opinión de los estudiantes de carreras sanitarias sobre problemas éticos relacionados con las personas VIH+ en centros docentes, de trabajo y sanitarios. Arch Prev Riesgos Labor [Internet]. 2012 [acesso 9 maio 2019];15(1):13-9. Disponível: https://bit.ly/2WYzzzM
    » https://bit.ly/2WYzzzM
  • 48
    Soskolne CL. Ethical, social, and legal issues surrounding studies of susceptible populations and individuals. Environ Health Perspect [Internet]. 1997 [acesso 9 maio 2019];105(supl 4):837-41. DOI: 10.1289/ehp.97105s4837
    » https://doi.org/10.1289/ehp.97105s4837
  • 49
    Viveka D. Nursing ethics comes of age in India. Nurs Ethics [Internet]. 2014 [acesso 9 maio 2019];21(6):637-8. DOI: 10.1177/0969733014542557
  • 50
    Fortes PAC. Reflexões sobre o princípio ético da justiça distributiva aplicado aos sistemas de saúde. In: Fortes PAC, Zoboli ELCP, organizadores. Bioética e saúde pública. São Paulo: Loyola; 2003. p. 35-47.
  • 51
    Bavaresco A. Idealismo realista ou realismo idealista: Hegel & Marx. Veritas [Internet]. 2018 [acesso 28 ago 2019];63(1):355-75. DOI: 10.15448/1984-6746.2018.1.29831
  • 52
    Marx K, Engels F. A ideologia alemã. São Paulo: Boitempo; 2007.
  • 53
    Konder L. Ética marxista. In: Löwy M, organizador. O marxismo na América Latina: uma antologia de 1909 aos dias atuais. 4ª ed. São Paulo: Perseu Abramo; 2016. p. 585-90.
  • 54
    Cano MCA. La bioética desde una óptica marxista. Educ Méd Super [Internet]. 2008 [acesso 26 dez 2017];22(3). Disponível: https://bit.ly/2UXmwfD
    » https://bit.ly/2UXmwfD
  • 55
    Barroco MLS. Ética: fundamentos sócio-históricos. 3ª ed. São Paulo: Cortez; 2010. p. 84.
  • 56
    Vázquez AS. Ética. 37ª ed. Rio de Janeiro: Civilização Brasileira; 2017.
  • 57
    Elbe I. Pachukanis versus Lênin: dois paradigmas da crítica marxista do Estado. Margem Esquerda [Internet]. 2018 [acesso 26 dez 2017];(30):25-34. Disponível: https://bit.ly/2UP9Kj4
    » https://bit.ly/2UP9Kj4
  • 58
    Dias MCLC. O conceito de ética para Marx e Engels. Rev Dialectus [Internet]. 2016 [acesso 26 dez 2017];3(8):134-45. DOI: 10.30611/2016n8id5217
  • 59
    Valls Á. O que é ética. 9ª ed. São Paulo: Brasiliense; 1994.
  • 60
    Guedes É. A economia como sistema da representação em Karl Marx. São Leopoldo: Editora Unisinos; 2014.
  • 61
    Pachukanis EB. Teoria geral do direito e marxismo. São Paulo: Boitempo; 2017. p. 153.
  • 62
    Pachukanis EB. Op. cit. p. 154.
  • 63
    Turatti MCM. Antropologia, economia e marxismo: uma visão crítica. São Paulo: Alameda; 2011.
  • 64
    Pachukanis EB. Op. cit. p. 155.
  • 65
    Goldim JR. O imperativo categórico. UFRGS [Internet]. 2003 [acesso 29 jan 2019]. Disponível: https://bit.ly/2R0l0rW
    » https://bit.ly/2R0l0rW
  • 66
    Vázquez AS. Ética e marxismo. In: Boron AA, Amadeo J, González S, organizadores. A teoria marxista hoje: problemas e perspectivas [Internet]. Buenos Aires: Clacso; 2007 [acesso 29 jan 2019]. p. 316-27. Disponível: https://bit.ly/3aDejUj
    » https://bit.ly/3aDejUj
  • 67
    Márkus G. Marxismo e antropologia: o conceito de essência humana na filosofia de Marx. São Paulo: Expressão Popular; 2015.
  • 68
    Bornheim G. O sujeito e a norma. In: Novaes A, organizador. Ética: vários autores. São Paulo: Companhia das Letras; 2007. p. 246-60.
  • 69
    Cunha LLN, Dias MCLC. O significado das questões ético-morais para Marx. Saberes [Internet]. 2016 [acesso 29 jan 2019];1(13):35-48. Disponível: https://bit.ly/2X1PQnS
    » https://bit.ly/2X1PQnS
  • 70
    Pachukanis EB. Op. cit. p. 162.

Publication Dates

  • Publication in this collection
    26 June 2020
  • Date of issue
    Apr-Jun 2020

History

  • Received
    7 Mar 2019
  • Reviewed
    7 Oct 2019
  • Accepted
    29 Mar 2020
Conselho Federal de Medicina SGAS 915, lote 72, CEP 70390-150, Tel.: (55 61) 3445-5932, Fax: (55 61) 3346-7384 - Brasília - DF - Brazil
E-mail: bioetica@portalmedico.org.br