Acessibilidade / Reportar erro

Resumption and last resort

Pronomes resumptivos e a condição de último recurso

Abstracts

This paper discusses the derivation of definite and indefinite relative clauses in Lebanese Arabic. The two types of relative clause are similar in that they require resumptive pronouns and do not exhibit island effects. Based on reconstruction effects, I however argue that definite relatives may be either base-generated or derived by movement, whereas indefinite relatives can only be base-generated.

Relative Clauses; Resumptive Pronouns; Reconstruction; Lebanese Arabic


Este trabalho discute a derivação de orações relativas definidas e indefinidas em árabe libanês. Os dois tipos de relativas são semelhantes na medida em que ambos requerem pronomes resumptivos e não exibem efeitos de ilha. Com base em efeitos de reconstrução, eu argumento no entanto que as relativas definidas podem ser tanto geradas na base, quanto derivadas por movimento, enquanto as relativas indefinidas só podem ser geradas na base.

Orações Relativas; Pronomes Resumptivos; Reconstrução; Árabe Libanês


Resumption and Last Resort* * For his comments on an earlier draft of this paper, I wish to thank Jairo Nunes. This paper was completed in the spring of 1996.

(Pronomes Resumptivos e a Condição de último Recurso)

Joseph AOUN

(University of Southern California)

ABSTRACT: This paper discusses the derivation of definite and indefinite relative clauses in Lebanese Arabic. The two types of relative clause are similar in that they require resumptive pronouns and do not exhibit island effects. Based on reconstruction effects, I however argue that definite relatives may be either base-generated or derived by movement, whereas indefinite relatives can only be base-generated.

KEY WORDS: Relative Clauses, Resumptive Pronouns, Reconstruction, Lebanese Arabic

RESUMO: Este trabalho discute a derivação de orações relativas definidas e indefinidas em árabe libanês. Os dois tipos de relativas são semelhantes na medida em que ambos requerem pronomes resumptivos e não exibem efeitos de ilha. Com base em efeitos de reconstrução, eu argumento no entanto que as relativas definidas podem ser tanto geradas na base, quanto derivadas por movimento, enquanto as relativas indefinidas só podem ser geradas na base.

PALAVRAS-CHAVE: Orações Relativas, Pronomes Resumptivos, Reconstrução, Árabe Libanês

Introduction

The goal in this paper is to investigate some properties of resumptive pronouns in Lebanese Arabic (henceforth, LA).1 1 Issues related to weak crossover and resumption are discussed in Aoun and Choueiri (1996). Different analyses of weak crossover with constructions involving resumptives can be found in Demirdache (1991, to appear), Georgopoulos (1989), McCloskey (1990), Safir (to appear), and Sells (1984). I will do so by investigating the behavior of restrictive relative constructions in LA, which are generated with the resumptive strategy.2 2 The topic of resumption has been the center of numerous studies. I have mainly relied on work done by the following authors: Borer (1983), Cinque (1990), Demirdache (1991), Doron (1983), Eid (1977, 1983), Engdhal (1986), McCloskey (1990), Sells (1984), Shlonsky (1992), and Zaenen, Engdahl, and Maling (1981).

LA distinguishes between definite relative constructions and indefinite ones. Definite relatives are generated with a definite complementizer; indefinite relatives are generated with no complementizer.

The following generalizations hold true in LA:

Simplifying the features of the analysis, the behavior of the two types of relatives is accounted for under the following assumptions:

In definite relatives, movement is triggered to check features of the complementizer. In indefinite relatives, on the other hand, there is no complementizer and nothing forces movement to occur. As such, it does not occur. In other words, in LA, movement in relative constructions appears to be a last resort strategy.

The theoretical implications of the analysis of resumptives will be discussed in the conclusion.

1. Restrictive relatives in Lebanese Arabic

As stated in the introduction, restrictive relative clauses in LA fall into two categories: restrictive relatives with a definite relativized DP (definite relatives) and restrictive relatives with an indefinite relativized DP (indefinite relatives).3 3 In this paper, I restrict our investigation of relative constructions in LA to restrictive relatives. I will henceforth refer to them using the general term relative clause.

Definite relatives always occur with the complementizer yalli:4 4 yalli is specific to relative constructions. Sentential complements in LA are introduced by nno, as illustrated below:

Indefinite relatives on the other hand cannot occur with yalli; as a matter of fact, indefinite relatives have no complementizer:

What unifies these two types of relatives is that they are both formed with the resumptive strategy: in constructions with definite relatives and indefinite relatives, the relativized DP is generally related to a resumptive element that occurs within the relative clause. In non-subject positions,5 5 These non-subject positions include complements of verbs as well as complements of prepositions (i) or nouns (ii). the resumptive element is always realized as a clitic (or weak pronoun) (4a-5a). In subject position, the resumptive element may be realized as a tonic (or strong) pronoun (4b).6 In what follows, I investigate the resumptive strategy in both definite relatives and indefinite relatives.

1.1. Resumption in definite relatives

In definite relatives, gaps are prohibited in all non-subject positions. Instead, the relativized position is occupied by a resumptive clitic (6-7).

As (6) and (7) show, the resumptive clitic is required both in the higher object position and the embedded object position within the definite relative.

In subject position, a gap generally occurs:

The gap in subject can be identified as an instance of pro-drop, which is generally available in LA. It can occur, for instance, in the following contexts, which block movement:

In (9a-c), a gap can occur in subject position within islands, which are know to disallow wh-extraction.

Similarly, the relation between a resumptive clitic and the definite relativized DP is not sensitive to islands, as illustrated in (10-12).

Adopting the standard assumption that the absence of island effects indicates the absence of movement, it is possible to account for the distribution of resumptive pronouns within definite relatives in LA by generating those constructions without movement. In what follows, I examine how this account extends to indefinite relatives.

1.2. Resumption in indefinite relatives

Like definite relatives, indefinite relatives also require a resumptive clitic in all non-subject positions (13-14).

In subject positions (15a-b) instead, a gap occurs:

As can be observed in (16-18) below, the relation between the indefinite relativized DP and the resumptive element is not sensitive to islands:

Since it occurs in island contexts (16b-18b), the gap in subject position within the indefinite relatives can be identified as the null pronominal element pro. Indefinite relatives pattern together with definite relatives in allowing resumptive pronouns to occur within islands. It is therefore possible to generalize the analysis put forward for definite relatives to include indefinite relatives; in this case, indefinite relatives would also be generated without involving movement.

2. Restrictive relatives in LA and movement: reconstruction effects

The discussion in the previous section highlighted the absence of island effects within restrictive relatives in LA. It was suggested that this characteristic indicates that the derivation of restrictive relatives does not involve movement. This being the case, we expect relative clauses in LA not to display any effects of movement. In what follows, I show that this expectation is not always fulfilled and that movement may be involved in the generation of relative clauses in LA.

2.1. Reconstruction within definite relatives

In Chomsky 1993, it is argued that reconstruction is a property of chains generated by (non-L-related or A'-) movement. In view of the non-movement analysis suggested above, we expect definite relatives in LA never to display reconstruction effects; as can be observed below, this expectation is not always fulfilled.

The sentences in (19) can be represented as in (20a-b) (irrelevant details omitted):

In (19), the pronoun contained within the definite relativized DP SSuura taba

bn-a 'the picture of her son' can be bound from within the relative clause by the QP kll mwazzafe 'every employee'. This bound reading is represented in (20a-b) by coindexing the pronoun with the QP. The availability of the bound pronoun reading may be taken to indicate that the pronoun within the definite relativized DP is interpreted from the position of the resumptive pronoun, a position which is c-commanded by the QP kll mwazzafe 'every employee'.7 7 I will discuss how this interpretation obtains in section 3.3.2.

However, reconstruction is not always available: for instance, reconstruction is not available when the definite relativized DP and the re sumptive element to which it is related are separated by an island (21-23).

The sentences in (21-23) have the representation in (24) (irrelevant details omitted):

As indicated by the ungrammaticality of (24), the bound reading of the pronoun contained within the definite relativized DP SSuura taba

bn-a 'the picture of her son' cannot obtain. That is, at LF the relativized DP containing the pronoun cannot reconstruct to a position c-commanded by the QP kll mwazzafe 'every employee'.

Summarizing, we have observed in this section, that reconstruction is available in definite relatives when the resumptive element does not occur within an island. This generalization is illustrated in (25):

At this point, it is possible to assume that reconstruction is only tied to islands: that is, reconstruction effects occur when no island intervenes between the relativized DP and the RP to which it is related. Alternatively, one may assume, as I have done so far, that reconstruction is tied to movement. Under the latter assumption, the selective availability of reconstruction in definite relatives in LA indicates that movement is available for the generation of those constructions only when the island constraints are not violated: a derivation involving movement is thus available for the representation in (25a), but not for the one in (25b).

The working of reconstruction in indefinite relatives will provide motivation for the second assumption. It will appear that with indefinite relatives corresponding to the representation in (26), reconstruction is not available:

The contrast between (25a) and (25b) shows that the absence of islands is a necessary condition for the availability of reconstruction. The unavailability of reconstruction in (26) will indicate that this condition is not sufficient to account for the cases in which reconstruction does in fact occur. Hence the assumption that reconstruction is tied to movement.

2.2. Reconstruction within indefinite relatives

As stated in the preceding paragraph, indefinite relatives do not display any reconstruction effects. That is, a pronoun contained within an indefinite relativized DP can never be bound by a QP in the indefinite relative clause. This generalization is illustrated below:

The facts illustrated in (27) may be represented as in (28a-b) respectively:

Even when the RP does not occur in an island, the indefinite relativized DP with which this RP is coindexed cannot reconstruct below the QP in the indefinite relative (27). The contrast between definite relatives and indefinite relatives with respect to reconstruction, i.e. the contrast between (28) and (25), is accounted for under the assumptions that reconstruction is tied to movement and that no movement is involved in the generation of indefinite relatives.8 8 Obviously, indefinite relatives do not display reconstruction effects when the indefinite relativized DP is related to a resumptive element which occurs in an island: In what follows, I offer an account for the discrepancy between definite relatives and indefinite relatives with respect to the availability of movement.

3. Generation of definite relatives

An analysis which allows movement in the derivation of definite relatives but not indefinite relatives raises the following questions:

I start by investigating the properties of definite relatives.

3.1. Morphosyntactic properties of yalli

As noted earlier, the morpheme yalli occurs only in restrictive relatives that are definite, and is itself definite, as the following discussion indicates.9 9 The counterpart of yalli in Standard Arabic ( a)llaDi occurs in definite relatives but not in indefinite relatives. It is morphologically definite: it is introduced by the definite article al-.

In LA, nouns and their modifiers agree in definiteness (30).

In (30a-b), the adjectives agree in definiteness with the nouns they modify: In (30a), the adjective l-diid (the new) occurs with the definite article al- since the noun it modifies, i.e. l-kteeb (the book), is definite. On the other hand, the adjective diid (new) in (30b) does not occur with the definite article al- since the noun it modifies, i.e. kteeb (book), is indefinite.

Furthermore, a sentence where the noun and its modifier do not show agreement in definiteness would be ungrammatical:

Consider now the following sentences involving relative clauses:

The contrast between (32a) and (32b) indicates that yalli is definite: yalli can only occur when the relativized DP is definite. Assuming yalli to be a complementizer generated in the head C of the relative clause, this would mean that the relative clause yalli Talabtii (that you ordered) in (32a) is definite, thus matching the relativized DP l-kteeb (the book). The ungrammaticality of (32b) is the result of the clash between the definiteness of the relative clause and the indefiniteness of the relativized DP.

In addition to being [+definite], yalli also bears j-features. Generally, null subjects in LA occur in the context of overt agreement, as illustrated below:

In (33a), a null subject occurs with a verbal predicate inflected for person, number, and gender (j-features). In (33b), a null subject is prohibited; the prepositional predicate doesn't have j-features. (33c) is well-formed only when the complementizer

nno has j-features that identify the embedded null subject.

Turning back to definite relatives, the grammaticality of (34) below indicates that yalli, like nno, bears the necessary j-features in the context of which null subjects occur.10 10 Cross-linguistic data from Standard Arabic provide motivation for the assumption that the definite relative complementizer bears j-features, and a case feature as well:

The prepositional predicate bl-beet ('in the house') obviously does not show overt subject agreement. If yalli did not agree with the null subject of this predicate, we would expect this sentence to be non-well-formed on a par with (33b), which is contrary to fact.

Assume then that the features borne by yalli, i.e., its [+definite] feature and j-features, need to be checked in the course of the derivation.11 11 Although the complementizer yalli matches the relativized DP in definiteness, it cannot be said that yalli checks this feature against that of the relativized DP, since yalli can occur in headless relatives, unless headless relatives occur with a non-overt pronominal:

Summarizing, in this section I have discussed the morphosyntactic properties of yalli, the element which introduces definite relatives in LA. I have assumed that:

It is (35c) that provides the motivation for movement in definite relatives in LA: the necessity to check the features of the complementizer triggers movement in those constructions.

3.2.Yalli and the nature of the moving element

This movement can be characterized as covert, i.e. it doesn't involve pied-piping of a category. The moving element is then a bundle of formal features, which include the feature [+definite] and the relevant j-features. Within the minimalist theory of Move a, the movement of these features will involve adjunction to the complementizer yalli, which heads the relative clause.

The formal features of yalli can only be checked by those of a DP, Pps being obviously not specified for definiteness, as well as j-features. This DP cannot be the counterpart of a wh-element: wh-elements are not definite in LA, as shown below.

Recall that in LA, the adjective and the DP it modifies agree in definiteness. The contrast between (36a) and (36b) indicates that the adjective modifying the wh-phrase ayya tlmiiz (which student) cannot be introduced by the definite article. This contrast shows that wh-phrases are indeed indefinite. Our conclusion is further confirmed by relative clauses modifying wh-phrases. These relative clauses cannot be introduced by yalli:

Since relative clauses introduced by yalli can only modify definite relativized Dps, the ungrammaticality of (37a) confirms the non-definite nature of wh-elements in LA.

In brief, the element that checks the features of yalli can be identified as a set of formal features. This set comprises the features [+definite], j-features, and case. I identify this set with the null pronominal element pro. pro, like all pronouns in LA, is related to an argument position: in LA, there are no pronouns corresponding to adjuncts. As a consequence, we expect an adjunct not to be relativized in LA, as illustrated by the ungrammaticality of (38).12 12 In the well-formed phrases (i-iii), the relativized DP corresponds to a prepositional complement within the relative clause.

3.3.The working of movement and reconstruction in definite relatives

The discussion so far has provided answers to three of the four questions in (29). Movement in definite relatives was motivated by the need for the relative complementizer to check its [+definite] feature and j-features (question (29a)) against those of an element which adjoins to it (question (29c)). The element that checks these features was identified as pro (question (29b)), characterized here as a set of formal features. In the light of this analysis, I examine the working of movement and reconstruction within definite relatives.

3.3.1. Movement and minimality in definite relatives

Yalli, which occurs in all definite relatives in LA, bears features which need to be checked by pro. Furthermore, we have noted that in definite relatives, the selective availability of reconstruction indicates that movement is available in those constructions. In other words, to satisfy the morphological requirements of the complementizer yalli the following two scenarios are possible: (i) either pro is moved to COMP (39a) or (ii) pro is directly generated in COMP (39b).

In the sentences where the relativized DP is separated from the resumptive pronoun by an island, only the representation in (39b) is available. Since movement of pro is not possible from within an island, the features of yalli can only be checked by generating a null pro directly in COMP. In that case, pro is coindexed with another null pronominal in an argument position within the relative clause. On the other hand, when no island intervenes between the relativized DP and the resumptive pronoun, the representation in (39a) is available for definite relatives, in addition to the representation which doesn't involve movement (39b). In (39a) movement of pro has occurred from within the relative clause to COMP.13 13 The existence of the two representations in (42) for definite relatives does not raise a question of economy. Assuming that in evaluating derivations for economy, only convergent alternatives with the same numeration are considered, neither (42a) nor (42b) could have a blocking effect on the other, since they don't involve the same numeration: in (42b), pro is selected twice for the initial array whereas, in (42a), it is selected only once (see Aoun and Benmamoun (1998)).

The movement analysis sketched in (39a) above raises a question with respect to minimality. Consider constructions such as (40) below, in which the movement of the object pro to yalli crosses the subject pro:

In (40) movement of the object pro to yalli should violate minimality. Indeed, there is a shorter derivation which involves moving the subject pro of the embedded clause instead. In other words, we are lead to expect sentence (40) to be non well-formed, which is not the case.

However, under a theory which takes minimality to be sensitive to the feature being checked (see Chomsky 1995), we can account for the well-formedness of (40). yalli bears the same j-features as the relativized DP SSuura taba tlmiiza 'the picture of her student'. The pro subject of the embedded verb in (40), being masculine, cannot check those features. Raising pro from the embedded object position to yalli crosses the embedded subject pro but doesn't violate minimality, since the pro being crossed doesn't bear the relevant j-features that need to be checked in yalli.

3.3.2. pro and reconstruction of definite relativized DPs

As stated in the previous section, the generation of definite relatives may involve movement (39a) or not (39b). Following Chomsky (1977), Williams (1980) and Borer (1984), I assume that the relative clause and the relativized DP form a predication structure: the relative clause constitutes a complex predicate coindexed with the relativized DP, the subject of this predication. The complex predicate must contain an open position which functions as the predicate variable (the trace in (39a) and pro in (39b) within the definite relative).

We are now in a position to discuss how reconstruction operates within definite relatives. Consider the following English facts (Barss 1986, Hornstein 1984):

Although the c-command requirement on bound pronouns fails to apply in (41), the pronoun his can still be bound by the QP every Englishman. In (41), the DP his last poem is coindexed with the relative clause via predication. What, which bears the same index as his last poem, can be interpreted as a 'copy' of this DP. Informally, at LF, his last poem, what, and the trace of what within the relative clause, form an extended chain. Hence, the availability of the bound pronoun reading in (41).

Turning to the representations in (39), the relativized DP, the relative clause, and the pro in COMP are all coindexed. However, reconstruction is available in (39a) but not in (39b). In (39a), the pro and its trace form a chain generated by movement. In (39b), the two distinct pro do not form a movement chain. Since reconstruction occurs only with chains generated by movement, reconstruction will be available in (39a) but not in (39b) (see the conclusion for further discussion).

3.3.3. Reconstruction of definite relativized DPs

Having examined how reconstruction of the relativized DP obtains, I now identify the position to which the fronted pro reconstructs.

A close look at definite relatives in LA reveals an asymmetry between preverbal and postverbal subjects with respect to reconstruction.14 14 A contrast similar to the one illustrated in (42-43) was first pointed out for Spanish Left Dislocation constructions by Zubizarreta 1993. That is, a pronoun contained in a definite relativized DP can be bound by a preverbal subject QP (42a-43a), but not by a postverbal subject QP (42b-43b).

The contrast between (42a) and (43a) on one hand, and (42b) and (43b) on the other, indicates that reconstruction is to a position lower than the preverbal subject, but higher than the postverbal subject position. I assume, along with Aoun and Benmamoun (1998), that this position is within the clitic projection (ClitP) (Sportiche 1992), as in (44) below:

Given the structure in (44), it is clear that reconstruction cannot be to the object position, for instance. If this were the case, this position being c-commanded by both the preverbal and the postverbal subjects, the contrast observed in (42) and (43) would not arise.

The structure in (44) also leads us to expect that, in case the QP subject is generated in a clause higher than the one containing the RP, the preverbal/postverbal subject asymmetry will disappear. This expectation is fulfilled:

In (45), the bound reading is available: these sentences do not display any preverbal/postverbal subject asymmetry. In both (45a) and (45b), the QP kll mwazzafe 'every employee' and the resumptive clitic occur in different clauses. If pro in (45) reconstructs to the clitic projection, it will end up in a position c-commanded by both the preverbal subject QP (45a) and the postverbal subject QP (45b) of the higher clause.

More generally, in other contexts too pro does not seem to reconstruct below the clitic:

In (46a) but not in (46b), the object and the name Karim contained within the preverbal subject can be coreferential. In (46b), coindexing Karim with the object yields a violation of binding principle C. If the object pro were to reconstruct to the argument position, the sentence in (46b) would be well-formed, like (46a). This is contrary to fact.

We can conclude from the discussion so far that the pro related to an accusative resumptive pronoun cannot reconstruct below the ClitP. Assuming that pro is originally generated in the argument position and that it undergoes A-movement to ClitP, its behavior with respect to reconstruction may be accounted for along the following lines: According to Chomsky (1993), reconstruction is only a property of A'-chains; pro then will only reconstruct to the clitic projection and never below. Alternatively, one may assume that pro, being definite, needs to be interpreted within the clitic projection, outside the VP shell (see Diesing (1992), Beghelli and Stowell (1995)). Therefore, at LF, it will not reconstruct to its original position.15 15 When a subject gap occurs, I take definite relatives to be represented as follows: (ia) but not (ib) is generated by movement.

4. Generation of indefinite relatives

Earlier it was observed that indefinite relatives did not display reconstruction effects (see section 2.2.). Using reconstruction as a diagnostic for the availability of movement, the absence of reconstruction effects in indefinite relatives was interpreted as indicating the absence of movement in those constructions. In other words, restrictive relatives are not systematically generated via movement in LA. Movement is only available for definite relatives. It is motivated by the need to check the definiteness feature and j-features of the complementizer yalli. Indefinite relatives lack a complementizer; the motivation for movement is absent in those constructions. Move a being a Last Resort operation (see Chomsky 1995), the generation of indefinite relatives will not involve movement. This accounts for the discrepancy between definite relatives and indefinite relatives with respect to reconstruction effects (question (29d)).16 16 For a different analysis assuming that movement is involved in resumption within restrictive relatives, see the important work of Demirdache (1991). In her analysis, restrictive relatives involving resumptive pronouns are all generated by LF-movement of a null operator- identified as pro, to the Spec of Comp. This LF movement, she assumes, does not obey island constraints. An analysis along these lines does not account for the contrast observed between indefinite relatives and definite relatives in LA with respect to reconstruction. Moreover, I have shown that reconstruction, and therefore movement, in definite relatives is indeed sensitive to islands.

Two possible representations are consistent with the absence of movement in indefinite relatives: either (i) there is a pro directly generated in COMP within the indefinite relative, coindexed with another pro within the relative clause (47a), or (ii) there is no pro in the indefinite COMP and pro occurs only within the indefinite relative (47b).17 17 Recall that the resumptive pro within the indefinite relative provides the predicate variable which is coindexed with the subject of predication, i.e. the relativized DP. Since pro can only be related to an argument position in LA, I can account for the fact that adjuncts cannot 'head' indefinite relatives, as illustrated below:

5. Conclusion: the raising analysis revisited

In this paper, we have examined the properties of restrictive relatives in LA. We have found the following generalizations to hold true of these constructions:

To account for the above generalizations, I have argued for the following analysis:

In both indefinite and definite relatives, the relativized DP ends up coindexed with a pro. Since pro can only be related to argument positions, it follows that adjuncts in LA cannot be relativized, as seen in (41), repeated here for convenience, and in (50):

As a final discussion, I would like to reconsider the working of reconstruction in definite relatives generated by movement. To account for the fact that a definite relativized DP can be interpreted with respect to a position within the relative clause, I assumed that this relativized DP, the fronted pro and its trace, form an extended chain (see section 3.3.2.). One might suggest an alternative analysis which can account for the reconstruction effects observed in definite relatives, in a more straightforward fashion; that is, the raising analysis argued for in Vergnaud 1974, 1985 and more recently in Kayne 1994. If the relativized DP is itself fronted from within the relative clause to check the necessary features of yalli, the reconstruction effects are to be expected. In the cases where movement cannot be involved, i.e. when the relativized site occurs within an island or when it corresponds to an indefinite DP, the relativized DP is directly generated in its surface position, coindexed with a null pro in the relativized site and no reconstruction occurs.

Under a raising analysis of the relativized DP, the obligatoriness of resumptive elements within definite relatives remains unaccounted for: if it is the relativized DP, and not pro, that raises to COMP, why is it necessary for the relative clause to contain a resumptive clitic in object positions? Why can't a gap occur in these positions?

As can be seen in the following examples, a DP in LA can be topicalized (51a) or clitic-left dislocated (51b). In (51a), the DP is coindexed with a gap, and in (51b), with a resumptive clitic:

Similarly, wh-elements in LA may be fronted and coindexed with a gap (52a) or a resumptive clitic (52b):

Why is it then that definite relativized DPs cannot be coindexed with a gap? Under an analysis which considers that the relativized DP itself raises in definite relatives, the answer is not obvious. However, under an account that assumes pro raising to COMP, the answer is rather straightforward: pro in object positions is always generated with a clitic, as evidenced by the ungrammaticality of (53b), below:

The ungrammaticality of a definite relativized DP coindexed with a gap in LA (54) reduces to the ungrammaticality of (53b):

In the same vein, I argued that adjuncts in LA cannot be relativized because pro cannot be generated in non-argument positions. Once again, under a raising analysis of the relativized DP, it is not clear how to exclude sentence (41) in LA, given the well-formedness of the English sentence in (55):

Thus, (definite) relatives in English differ from the definite relatives in LA, in at least the following respects:

In LA, wh-elements are indefinite (see section 3.2.) and thus cannot co-occur in COMP with the definite relative complementizer yalli. Since only pro can be fronted to COMP in definite relatives, only arguments can be relativized.

In brief, the difference between relative clauses in English and Lebanese Arabic may be accounted for in case Vergnaud's raising analysis is adopted for English and the pro raising analysis is adopted for LA.18 18 A similar proposal is put forward by Demirdache (to appear) to account for the following facts; Doron (1982) and Sells (1984), indicate that restrictive relatives with gaps (as in English) differ from restrictive relatives with RPs (as in Hebrew) in their interpretation:

SAFIR, K. (to appear) Derivation, Representation and Resumption: The Domain of Weak Crossover. Linguistic Inquiry.

I will illustrate our generalizations using constructions with accusative resumptive clitics. However, these generalizations hold true of resumptive clitics which are complements of prepositions and nouns as well.

6In this paper I will deal only with restrictive relatives involving resumptive clitics. The reader is referred to Aoun and Choueiri 1996 and Aoun, Choueiri, and Hornstein 1998 for a discussion of strong pronouns that occur as resumptive elements. For an evaluation of the difference between strong and weak pronouns in null subject languages, the reader is referred to Kato (1999). It should be noted that the analysis argued for in this paper may be extended to cases of resumption involving strong pronouns.

As can be observed in (i) above, the Standard Arabic counterpart of yalli is inflected for person, gender, and number. In addition, the sentences in (i) illustrate that the relative clause complementizer allaDi displays overt agreement in case with the relativized DP.

The sentence in (i) contrasts with the one in (ii) below where the head of the relative is related to the complement position of a preposition:

(ia) is ambiguous between a specific and a non-specific reading of the relativized head

ha-i'a ('the woman'). That is, (ia) can be used in a context where Dani is looking for a woman who has a certain property, but he doesn't know her identity yet (non-specific reading). (ia) can also be used in a context where Dani is looking for a specific woman, say, Rina. (ib), on the other hand, is unambiguous; it has only the interpretation where the relativized head

ha-i'a ('the woman') refers to a specific person, whose identity is known to Dani. Demirdache (to appear) accounts for the contrast between (ia) and (ib) by assuming Vergnaud's raising analysis for (ia) and pro raising for (ib).

However, the facts described above for Hebrew do not carry over to LA: in LA, the equivalent of (ib), below, is ambiguous. It is interpreted as (ia).

LA, unlike Hebrew, does not allow gaps in object position within headed restrictive relatives. In LA, a contrast similar to the one in (i) seems to exist only when an alternation between gaps and resumptive pronouns is available. This is the case with wh-interrogatives:

(iiia) is ambiguous but not (iiib). (iiib) admits only a specific reading.

  • AOUN, J. (1993) The Syntax of Doubled Arguments. International Journal of Basque Linguistics and Philology 27, 709-730.
  • žžžžž & E. BENMAMOUN (1998) Minimality, Reconstruction, and PF-Movement. Linguistic Inquiry 29: 569-597.
  • žžžžž & Y.-H. A. Li (1990) Minimal Disjointness. Linguistics 28: 189-203.
  • žžžžž & L. CHOUEIRI (1996) Resumptive epithets. Ms., University of Southern California, Los Angeles, California.
  • BARSS, A. (1986) Chains and Anaphoric Dependence: On Reconstruction and Its Implications. Doctoral Dissertation, MIT, Cambridge, Mass.
  • BEGHELLI, F. & T. STOWELL (TO appear) Distributivity and Negation. In Ways of Scope Taking. Anna Szablocsi (ed.). Boston: Kluwer Academic Publisher.
  • BORER, H. (1984) Restrictive Relatives in Modern Hebrew. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 2, 219-260.
  • BRESNAN, J. & J. GRIMSHAW (1978) The Syntax of Free Relatives in English. Linguistic Inquiry 9, 331-391.
  • CHOMSKY, N. (1977) On Wh-Movement. In P. Culicover, T. Wasow, and A. Akmadjian (eds.) Formal Syntax New York: Academic Press.
  • žžžžž (1993) A Minimalist Program for Linguistic Theory. In: The View from Building 20: Essays in Linguistics in Honor of Sylvain Bromberger, eds. Kenneth Hale and Samuel Jay Keyser, 1-52. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
  • žžžžž (1995) The Minimalist Program Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
  • CINQUE, G. (1990) Types of A'-Dependencies Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
  • DEMIRDACHE, H. (1991) Resumptive Chains in Restrictive Relatives, Appositives, and Dislocation Structures. Doctoral Dissertation, MIT, Cambridge, Mass.
  • DIESING, M. (1992) Indefinites Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
  • DORON, E. (1982) On the Syntax and Semantics of Resumptive Pronouns. In Texas Linguistics Forum 19, ed. R. Bley-Vroman, 1-48. Austin, Texas.
  • EID, M. (1977) Arabic Relativization: Shadow Deletion or Pronoun Drop? Minnesota Papers in Linguistics and Philosophy of Language 4, 19-31.
  • žžžžž (1983) On the Communicative Function of Subject Pronouns in Arabic. Journal of Linguistics 19, 287-303.
  • ENGDHAL, E. (1986) Constituent Questions Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company.
  • FASSI FEHRI, A. (1982) Linguistique Arabe: Forme et Interprétation Rabat: Publications de la Faculté des Lettres et Sciences Humaines.
  • GEORGOPOULOS, C. (1989) Syntactic Variables: Resumptive Pronouns and A'-Binding in Palauan. Doctoral Dissertation, University of Utah.
  • HORNSTEIN, N. (1984) Logic as Grammar Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
  • HORVATH, J. (1986) FOCUS in the Theory of Grammar and the Syntax of Hungarian Dordrecht: Foris Publications.
  • KATO, M. (1999) Strong and Weak pronominals in the Null Subject Parameter. Probus 11: 1-37.
  • KAYNE, R. (1984) Connectedness and Binary Branching. Dordrecht: Foris Publications.
  • MCCLOSKEY, J. (1979) Transformational Syntax and Model-Theoretic Semantics: A Case Study in Modern Irish. Dordrecht: Reidel.
  • žžžžž (1990) Resumptive Pronouns, A'-Binding, and Levels of Representation in Irish. In Syntax and Semantics of the Modern Celtic Languages, Syntax and Semantics 23 New York: Academic Press.
  • MONTALBETTI, M. (1984) After Binding: On the Interpretation of Pronouns. Doctoral Dissertation, MIT, Cambridge, Mass.
  • REINHOLTZ, C. (1993) Verb Second, Mood, and Operator Licensing. Ms., USC, Los Angeles, California.
  • SELLS, P. (1984) Syntax and Semantics of Resumptive Pronouns. Doctoral Dissertation, University of Massachusetts at Amherst, Amherst, Massachusetts.
  • SHLONSKY, U. (1992) Resumptive Pronouns as a Last Resort. Linguistic Inquiry 23, 443-468.
  • SPORTICHE, D. (1992) Clitic Constructions. Ms., UCLA, Los Angeles, California.
  • VERGNAUD, J-R. 1974. French Relative Clauses. Doctoral Dissertation, MIT, Cambridge, Massachusetts.
  • žžžžž 1985. DJpendences et Niveaux de ReprJsentation en Syntaxe Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
  • WILLIAMS, E. 1980. Predication. Linguistic Inquiry 11, 203-238.
  • ZAENEN, A., E. Engdahl & J. Maling. (1981). Resumptive Pronouns Can Be Syntactically Bound. Linguistic Inquiry 12, 679-682.
  • *
    For his comments on an earlier draft of this paper, I wish to thank Jairo Nunes. This paper was completed in the spring of 1996.
  • 1
    Issues related to weak crossover and resumption are discussed in Aoun and Choueiri (1996). Different analyses of weak crossover with constructions involving resumptives can be found in Demirdache (1991, to appear), Georgopoulos (1989), McCloskey (1990), Safir (to appear), and Sells (1984).
  • 2
    The topic of resumption has been the center of numerous studies. I have mainly relied on work done by the following authors: Borer (1983), Cinque (1990), Demirdache (1991), Doron (1983), Eid (1977, 1983), Engdhal (1986), McCloskey (1990), Sells (1984), Shlonsky (1992), and Zaenen, Engdahl, and Maling (1981).
  • 3
    In this paper, I restrict our investigation of relative constructions in LA to restrictive relatives. I will henceforth refer to them using the general term
    relative clause.
  • 4
    yalli is specific to relative constructions. Sentential complements in LA are introduced by
    nno, as illustrated below:
  • 5
    These non-subject positions include complements of verbs as well as complements of prepositions (i) or nouns (ii).
  • 7
    I will discuss how this interpretation obtains in section 3.3.2.
  • 8
    Obviously, indefinite relatives do not display reconstruction effects when the indefinite relativized DP is related to a resumptive element which occurs in an island:
  • 9
    The counterpart of
    yalli in Standard Arabic (
    a)llaDi occurs in definite relatives but not in indefinite relatives. It is morphologically definite: it is introduced by the definite article
    al-.
  • 10
    Cross-linguistic data from Standard Arabic provide motivation for the assumption that the definite relative complementizer bears j-features, and a case feature as well:
  • 11
    Although the complementizer
    yalli matches the relativized DP in definiteness, it cannot be said that
    yalli checks this feature against that of the relativized DP, since
    yalli can occur in headless relatives, unless headless relatives occur with a non-overt pronominal:
  • 12
    In the well-formed phrases (i-iii), the relativized DP corresponds to a prepositional complement within the relative clause.
  • 13
    The existence of the two representations in (42) for definite relatives does not raise a question of economy. Assuming that in evaluating derivations for economy, only convergent alternatives with the same numeration are considered, neither (42a) nor (42b) could have a blocking effect on the other, since they don't involve the same numeration: in (42b),
    pro is selected twice for the initial array whereas, in (42a), it is selected only once (see Aoun and Benmamoun (1998)).
  • 14
    A contrast similar to the one illustrated in (42-43) was first pointed out for Spanish Left Dislocation constructions by Zubizarreta 1993.
  • 15
    When a subject gap occurs, I take definite relatives to be represented as follows: (ia) but not (ib) is generated by movement.
  • 16
    For a different analysis assuming that movement is involved in resumption within restrictive relatives, see the important work of Demirdache (1991). In her analysis, restrictive relatives involving resumptive pronouns are all generated by LF-movement of a null operator- identified as
    pro, to the Spec of Comp. This LF movement, she assumes, does not obey island constraints. An analysis along these lines does not account for the contrast observed between indefinite relatives and definite relatives in LA with respect to reconstruction. Moreover, I have shown that reconstruction, and therefore movement, in definite relatives is indeed sensitive to islands.
  • 17
    Recall that the resumptive
    pro within the indefinite relative provides the predicate variable which is coindexed with the subject of predication, i.e. the relativized DP. Since
    pro can only be related to an argument position in LA, I can account for the fact that adjuncts cannot 'head' indefinite relatives, as illustrated below:
  • 18
    A similar proposal is put forward by Demirdache (to appear) to account for the following facts; Doron (1982) and Sells (1984), indicate that restrictive relatives with gaps (as in English) differ from restrictive relatives with RPs (as in Hebrew) in their interpretation:
  • Publication Dates

    • Publication in this collection
      11 Dec 2001
    • Date of issue
      2000
    Pontifícia Universidade Católica de São Paulo - PUC-SP PUC-SP - LAEL, Rua Monte Alegre 984, 4B-02, São Paulo, SP 05014-001, Brasil, Tel.: +55 11 3670-8374 - São Paulo - SP - Brazil
    E-mail: delta@pucsp.br