Acessibilidade / Reportar erro

Prospects for institutional research

1.

The need for institutional research

Everyone agrees that technology is important for economic development. But so too are organisations and other institutions. Douglass North (1971North, D.C. (1971), “Institutional change and economic growth”, The Journal of Economic History, Vol. 31 No. 1, pp. 118-125., p. 120) wrote:

The development of more efficient economic organisation is surely as important a part of the growth of the Western World as is the development of technology, and it is time it received equal attention. The few cases of which I am aware that have attempted to measure productivity change attributable to improving economic organisation certainly support this contention.

Here, North underlined the view that institutions (including organisations) were just as vital as technology in driving or enabling growth, but they had been unfortunately neglected. He went on to make several major contributions to our understanding of the role of institutions in economic history and economic development. He stimulated many others to contribute in the same vein and he won the Nobel Prize in Economics for his efforts.

But despite North’s achievements, there is still a prominent view in some quarters that economic growth and development are largely about physical inputs and technology. Yet the “social technology” [as Nelson and Sampat (2001)Nelson, R. and Sampat, B.N. (2001), “Making sense of institutions as a factor shaping economic performance”, Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, Vol. 44 No. 1, pp. 31-54. have put it] of institutions is equally vital. We need to build the interdisciplinary field of institutional research, to further contribute to our understanding of institutions and their role in socio-economic activity.

There is a useful precedent. Since the 1980s, there has been a remarkable global growth of research efforts in universities devoted to the new interdisciplinary field of innovation studies: it now sports its own institutes, academic positions, journals and degrees (Martin, 2012Martin, B.R. (2012), “The evolution of science policy and innovation studies”, Research Policy, Vol. 41 No. 7, pp. 1219-1239.).

The massive success of innovation studies in attracting funding and researchers provides hope and inspiration for a new interdisciplinary field of institutional research. The case for the interdisciplinary study of institutions matches the case for the interdisciplinary study of technology. To understand economic institutions fully we need to draw from disciplines as diverse as sociology, politics, philosophy, law, history and psychology and economics itself.

The interdisciplinary field of institutional research can appeal to the fact that institutional innovation is just as important as technological innovation, and the social technology of institutions is just as important as the technology of materials. This essay considers some of the fundamental concepts and research problems that this embryonic field uses and encounters.

There are important debates about the definition of an institution, but a consensus is emerging that all institutions are systems of embedded social rules, even if that definition needs nuancing in some ways and some important controversies remain (Ostrom, 1990Ostrom, E. (1990), Governing the Commons: The Evolution of Institutions for Collective Action, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.; Searle, 1995Searle, J.R. (1995), The Construction of Social Reality, Allen Lane, London.; Hindriks and Guala, 2015Hindriks, F. and Guala, F. (2015), “Institutions, rules, and equilibria: a unified theory”, Journal of Institutional Economics, Vol. 11 No. 3, pp. 459-480.; Hodgson, 2006Hodgson, G.M. (2006), “What are institutions?”, Journal of Economic Issues, Vol. 40 No. 1, pp. 1-25., 2015bHodgson, G.M. (2015b), “On defining institutions: rules versus equilibria”, Journal of Institutional Economics, Vol. 11 No. 3, pp. 499-505., 2019Hodgson, G.M. (2019), “Taxonomic definitions in social science, with firms, markets and institutions as case studies”, Journal of Institutional Economics, (forthcoming).; Guala, 2016Guala, F. (2016), Understanding Institutions: The Science and Philosophy of Living Together, Princeton University Press, Princeton and London.). Such rules include laws, customs and established norms of behaviour. Consequently, systems of rules such as languages and codes of etiquette are institutions. Money is an institution because it entails shared rules concerning its value, function and exchangeability.

Organisations such as states, banks, firms and universities, are systems of rules, and hence also institutions. North has been widely interpreted as denying that organisations are institutions, but in correspondence he denied this (Hodgson, 2006Hodgson, G.M. (2006), “What are institutions?”, Journal of Economic Issues, Vol. 40 No. 1, pp. 1-25.). Organisations are special institutions because they entail rules of membership and sovereignty. They are a sub-area of institutional analysis in their own right (Powell and DiMaggio, 1991Powell, W.W. and DiMaggio, PJ. (Eds) (1991), The New Institutionalism in Organizational Analysis, University of Chicago Press, Chicago and London.).

Institutional studies would rightly prioritise the study of those institutions that impact upon the economy. Other institutions, such as language, are studied elsewhere (in linguistics). Demonstrations of the positive or negative effects on institutions on economic activity are important to gain public support and funding for this field of research.

The basic definition of an institution as a system of established social rules raises a number of important questions that are central to institutional analysis. For instance, how are rules established in a community? Can some institutions arise spontaneously, or do some require some powerful authority? Why do people follow rules? Is rule-following a matter of habit or rational calculation? To what degree can rules be violated without endangering the survival of the institution? How do rules change? What happens when different rules prescribe conflicting or mutually incompatible actions? And so on.

Posing these questions raises issues of power, psychology, politics, law and much else. Hence such research must draw upon multiple disciplines. The fact that economic institutions are uppermost does not, in particular, mean that the rational utility-maximiser of mainstream economics has priority over other psycho-philosophical depictions or explanations of individual behaviour. Rather than the dogmatic application of one particular approach, it is a question of what theories are most useful and enlightening in their explanations of the institutional phenomena under study.

Major contributions have already been made to the study of economic institutions by economists (both the original and new institutionalists), sociologists, political scientists, lawyers, philosophers and others. We need to combine these resources to develop institutional research.

It is important to acknowledge that institutional research has already made major progress, notably for example in the area of economic development. For instance, the literature on “legal origins” claims to show that countries adopting an Anglo-American style system of common law during and after colonialisation have experienced stronger economic growth (La Porta et al., 1999La Porta, R., Lopez-de-Silanes, F., Shleifer, A. and Vishny, R. (1999), “The quality of government”, Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, Vol. 15 No. 1, pp. 222-279., 2008La Porta, R., Lopez-de-Silanes, F. and Shleifer, A. (2008), “The economic consequences of legal origins”, Journal of Economic Literature¸, Vol. 46 No. 2, pp. 285-332.). Daron Acemoglu et al. (2005)Acemoglu, D., Johnson, S. and Robinson, J.A. (2005), “Institutions as a fundamental cause of long-run growth”, in Aghion, P. and Durlauf, S.N. (Eds), Handbook of Economic Growth: Volume 1A, Elsevier, Amsterdam, pp. 385-472. and his colleagues have proposed a different institutional theory. In North America, Australia and a few other places, the British colonisers made a deliberate attempt to set up legal and governmental institutions similar to those in their homeland. On the other hand, Britain and other European colonisers in Africa and South America, partly for reasons of disease in the tropical climate, were less inclined to build up European institutions. The colonisers focussed instead on the (often brutal) extraction of slaves and raw materials. According to Acemoglu et al. (2005)Acemoglu, D., Johnson, S. and Robinson, J.A. (2005), “Institutions as a fundamental cause of long-run growth”, in Aghion, P. and Durlauf, S.N. (Eds), Handbook of Economic Growth: Volume 1A, Elsevier, Amsterdam, pp. 385-472., these different founding institutions largely explain subsequent divergences of economic performance. Although particular theories are controversial, there is now widespread recognition that institutions are major factors in helping to explain economic development.

The following sections explore different aspects of institutional research. The discussion of individual motivation in section two shows the importance of psychology and philosophy in understanding individual motivations, particularly to follow or break institutional rules. The discussion of property rights and transaction costs in section three illustrates some of the severe difficulties that may arise when definitions of key terms are contested or unclear. The final section wraps up the essay by drawing together some prominent issues for the future.

2.

Institutions and individual motivation

Mainstream economists often assume that the individual acts like a rational calculator, maximising his or her own utility (or satisfaction). By contrast, many leading institutional economists – including Thorstein Veblen, John R. Commons, Ronald Coase, Douglass North and Oliver Williamson – have emphasised that the individual has limited information and is often unable to appraise the optimal position.

Important here is the idea of “bounded rationality” as developed by Herbert Simon (1957Simon, H.A. (1957), Models of Man: Social and Rational. Mathematical Essays on Rational Human Behavior in a Social Setting, Wiley, New York, NY., 1979Simon, H.A. (1979), “Rational decision making in business organizations”, American Economic Review, Vol. 69 No. 4, pp. 493-513.). He argued that individual rationality is “bounded” because of limited information, or limited capacity to analyse highly-complex situations or problems. Among others, North and Williamson both emphasised bounded rationality.

But in other respects there are big differences among institutional economists on how they understand individual motivation. Veblen (1899Veblen, T.B. (1899), The Theory of the Leisure Class: An Economic Study in the Evolution of Institutions, Macmillan, New York, NY., 1914Veblen, T.B. (1914), The Instinct of Workmanship, and the State of the Industrial Arts, Macmillan, New York, NY.) emphasised habits. These are formed through repetition of action or thought. They are influenced by prior activity and have durable, self-sustaining qualities. A habit may exist even if it is not manifest in behaviour. Habits can be triggered by an appropriate stimulus or context. Habit is a propensity to behave in particular ways in a particular class of situations (Dewey, 1922Dewey, J. (1922), Human Nature and Conduct: An Introduction to Social Psychology, 1st ed., Holt, New York, NY.; Camic, 1986Camic, C. (1986), “The matter of habit”, American Journal of Sociology, Vol. 91 No. 5, pp. 1039-1087.; Ouellette and Wood, 1998Ouellette, J.A. and Wood, W. (1998), “Habit and intention in everyday life: the multiple processes by which past behavior predicts future behavior”, Psychological Bulletin, Vol. 124 No. 1, pp. 54-74.; Wood et al., 2002Wood, W., Quinn, J.M. and Kashy, D. (2002), “Habits in everyday life: thought, emotion, and action”, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, Vol. 83 No. 6, pp. 1281-1297.).

The Veblenian concept of habit points to a crucial psychological mechanism by which institutions may affect individuals. Insofar as individuals are constrained or motivated to follow particular institutional norms or rules, then they tend to strengthen habits that are consistent with this behaviour. They may then rationalise these outcomes in terms of preference or choice (Hodgson, 2010Hodgson, G.M. (2010), “Choice, habit and evolution”, Journal of Evolutionary Economics, Vol. 20 No. 1, pp. 1-18.; Hodgson and Knudsen, 2004Hodgson, G.M. and Knudsen, T. (2004), “The complex evolution of a simple traffic convention: the functions and implications of habit”, Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, Vol. 54 No. 1, pp. 19-47.). According to this view, conscious choices are generally the outcome of habits, rather than the other way around.

Unlike other economists who take individual preferences as given, North (1981North, D.C. (1981), Structure and Change in Economic History, Norton, New York, NY., 1990North, D.C. (1990), Institutions, Institutional Change and Economic Performance, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge and New York, NY., 1994North, D.C. (1994), “Economic performance through time”, American Economic Review, Vol. 84 No. 3, pp. 359-367.) delved increasingly into how ideologies and other cognitive factors can frame our thoughts and preferences, in specific institutional and cultural environments. He pointed to the limits of the standard rational-choice framework. He wrote:

History demonstrates that ideas, ideologies, myths, dogmas and prejudices matter; and an understanding of the way they evolve is necessary […]. Belief structures get transformed into societal and economic structures by institutions (North, 1994North, D.C. (1994), “Economic performance through time”, American Economic Review, Vol. 84 No. 3, pp. 359-367., pp. 362-363).

The starting point of a given individual (with fixed and enduring tastes and preferences) is problematic. It could be a temporary explanatory simplification, but ultimately, we need to probe further. Individual choice requires a conceptual framework to make sense of the world. The reception of information by individuals requires cognitive norms and frames to process and make sense of that information. As the original institutionalists argued, the transmission of information from individual to individual is impossible without immersion in a common culture, in which the individual learns the meaning and value of the information that is communicated.

There are also problems with the idea that we can explain institutions exclusively in terms of individuals. Even the most basic institutions involve human interaction, typically using some kind of language. Language itself is an institution (Searle, 1995Searle, J.R. (1995), The Construction of Social Reality, Allen Lane, London.; Hodgson, 2006Hodgson, G.M. (2006), “What are institutions?”, Journal of Economic Issues, Vol. 40 No. 1, pp. 1-25.). The communication of information itself requires shared conventions, rules, routines and norms. Consequently, any project to explain the emergence of institutions on the basis of given individuals runs into difficulties, particularly with regard to the conceptualisation of the initial state from which institutions are supposed to emerge (Aoki, 2001Aoki, M. (2001), Toward a Comparative Institutional Analysis, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.).

While individual motivations and incentives are important, among institutional researchers there are differences in views on how they are understood or modelled, ranging to proponents of utility maximisation (where all behaviour explained in terms of attempts to increase utility or satisfaction) to those like Coase and North who adopted a more nuanced view of human nature (which addresses multiple factors, including moral motivation and possible altruism, as well as greed). To understand human motivation there is a strong case for bringing in insights from psychology, as institutionalists such as Veblen (1899Veblen, T.B. (1899), The Theory of the Leisure Class: An Economic Study in the Evolution of Institutions, Macmillan, New York, NY., 1914Veblen, T.B. (1914), The Instinct of Workmanship, and the State of the Industrial Arts, Macmillan, New York, NY.) and North (1990)North, D.C. (1990), Institutions, Institutional Change and Economic Performance, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge and New York, NY. have argued. There is also a place for evolutionary ideas to help explain the nature of human motivation (Hodgson, 2013Hodgson, G.M. (2013), From Pleasure Machines to Moral Communities: An Evolutionary Economics without Homo Economicus, University of Chicago Press, Chicago.).

Relatedly, Knight (1992)Knight, J. (1992), Institutions and Social Conflict, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. criticised some prominent institutionalist literature for neglecting the importance of distributional and power considerations in the emergence and development of institutions. Importantly, Ostrom (1990)Ostrom, E. (1990), Governing the Commons: The Evolution of Institutions for Collective Action, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. emphasised the role of culture and norms in establishing and moulding both perceptions and behavioural interactions. Scott (1995)Scott, W.R. (1995), Institutions and Organizations, Sage, Thousand Oaks, CA and London. stressed the cognitive dimensions of institutions.

The idea that institutions help constitute individual motivation and behaviour admits an enhanced concept of power into institutional analysis. Power is exercised not only by forceful coercion or constraint. For Lukes (1974)Lukes, S. (1974), Power: A Radical View, Macmillan, London. the overemphasis on the coercive aspect of power ignores the way that it is often exercised more subtly, particularly by customs and institutions. In this way, perceptions and preferences are altered.

Accordingly, to understand individual motivation and action more fully, institutional research should draw on these and other insights from multiple disciplines.

3.

Property rights, law and transaction costs

The concept of property rights was stressed by original institutionalists such as Commons, as well as by more recent institutional researchers and those working on the “economics of property rights”. Property rights are seen as a vital component of the basic institutional structure of an economy with property ownership. But the concept of property rights has different definitions.

Some prominent economists have defined property rights in terms of control of an asset rather than moral or legal entitlement (Alchian, 1977Alchian, A.A. (1977), “Some implications of recognition of property right transaction costs”, in Brunner, K. (Ed.), Economics and Social Institutions: Insights from the Conferences on Analysis and Ideology, Martinus Nijhoff, Boston, MA, pp. 234-255.; Barzel, 1994Barzel, Y. (1994), “The capture of wealth by monopolists and the protection of property rights”, International Review of Law and Economics, Vol. 14 No. 4, pp. 393-409.). Such definitions have been criticised for mistaking de facto possession for legal property (Heinsohn and Steiger, 2013Heinsohn, G. and Steiger, O. (2013), Ownership Economics: On the Foundations of Interest, Money, Markets, Business Cycles and Economic Development, translated and edited by Frank Decker, Routledge, London and New York, NY.; Hodgson, 2015aHodgson, G.M. (2015a), Conceptualizing Capitalism: Institutions, Evolution, Future, University of Chicago Press, Chicago., 2015cHodgson, G.M. (2015c), “Much of the ‘Economics of property rights’ devalues property and legal rights”, Journal of Institutional Economics, Vol. 11 No. 4, pp. 683-709., 2017Hodgson, G.M. (2017), “1688 and all that: property rights, the glorious revolution and the rise of British capitalism”, Journal of Institutional Economics, Vol. 13 No. 1, pp. 79-107.). The upshot of the Alchian-Barzel definitions is that if a thief manages to keep stolen goods then he acquires a substantial property right to them, even if, on the contrary, legal or moral considerations would suggest that they remain the rightful property of their original owner. But it is misleading to describe the perceived ability to use or enjoy something as a “right”. Enjoyment or usage can occur without rights, and rights without usage or enjoyment. Possession is principally a relation between a person and a thing. It does not amount to legal ownership. Rights result from institutionalised rules involving assignments of benefit and duty (Honoré, 1961Honoré, A.M. (1961), “Ownership”, in Guest, A.G. (Ed.), Oxford Essays in Jurisprudence, Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp. 107-147, Reprinted in the Journal of Institutional Economics, Vol. 9 No. 2, June 2013, pp. 227-255.; Heinsohn and Steiger, 2013Heinsohn, G. and Steiger, O. (2013), Ownership Economics: On the Foundations of Interest, Money, Markets, Business Cycles and Economic Development, translated and edited by Frank Decker, Routledge, London and New York, NY.).

In contrast to Alchian and Barzel, Commons and Coase stressed that property must entail legal ownership, and hence, the legal system plays an important role in establishing deemed rights. Commons (1924Commons, J.R. (1924), Legal Foundations of Capitalism, Macmillan, New York, NY., p. 87) saw the contractual exchange of property as involving a minimum of not two parties but three, where the third is the state or a “superior authority”. Similarly, Coase (1959Coase, R.H. (1959), “The federal communications commission”, Journal of Law and Economics, Vol. 2 No. 1, pp. 1-40., p. 25) saw property rights as determined:

[…] by the law of property […]. One of the purposes of the legal system is to establish that clear delimitation of rights on the basis of which the transfer and recombination of rights can take place through the market.

By these definitions, property is a historically specific rather than a universal phenomenon (Honoré, 1961Honoré, A.M. (1961), “Ownership”, in Guest, A.G. (Ed.), Oxford Essays in Jurisprudence, Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp. 107-147, Reprinted in the Journal of Institutional Economics, Vol. 9 No. 2, June 2013, pp. 227-255.; HodgsonHodgson, G.M. (2015a), Conceptualizing Capitalism: Institutions, Evolution, Future, University of Chicago Press, Chicago., 2015a, 2015cHodgson, G.M. (2015c), “Much of the ‘Economics of property rights’ devalues property and legal rights”, Journal of Institutional Economics, Vol. 11 No. 4, pp. 683-709.).

The role of law is still debated among institutional researchers. Some treat law principally as a cost or constraint for individuals, who are simply maximising their “economic” benefits (Barzel, 1989Barzel, Y. (1989), Economic Analysis of Property Rights, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.). Others point out to evidence that suggests that many people obey the law because they believe it is the right thing to do, not simply because they fear punishment (Tyler, 1990Tyler, T.R. (1990), Why People Obey the Law, Yale University Press, New Haven.; Hodgson, 2015cHodgson, G.M. (2015c), “Much of the ‘Economics of property rights’ devalues property and legal rights”, Journal of Institutional Economics, Vol. 11 No. 4, pp. 683-709.). This raises the role of moral motivation, particularly when following accepted institutional rules (Smith, 1759Smith, A. (1759), The Theory of Moral Sentiments; or, An Essay towards an Analysis of the Principles by Which Men Naturally Judge concerning the Conduct and Character, First of Their Neighbours, and Afterwards of Themselves, Millar, and Kincaid and Bell, London and Edinburgh.; Sen, 1987Sen, A.K. (1987), On Ethics and Economics, Basil Blackwell, Oxford and New York, NY.; Hodgson, 2013Hodgson, G.M. (2013), From Pleasure Machines to Moral Communities: An Evolutionary Economics without Homo Economicus, University of Chicago Press, Chicago.; Smith, 2013Smith, V.L. (2013), “Adam smith: from propriety and sentiments to property and wealth”, Forum for Social Economics, Vol. 42 No. 4, pp. 283-297.).

Another important area of discussion is the role of law in constituting the modern firm and creating the possibility of corporate agency (Deakin et al., 2017Deakin, S., Gindis, D., Hodgson, G.M., Huang, K. and Pistor, K. (2017), “Legal institutionalism: capitalism and the constitutive role of law”, Journal of Comparative Economics, Vol. 45 No. 1, pp. 188-200.; Gindis, 2016Gindis, D. (2016), “Legal personhood and the firm: avoiding anthropomorphism and equivocation”, Journal of Institutional Economics, Vol. 12 No. 3, pp. 499-513.; Hodgson, 2015aHodgson, G.M. (2015a), Conceptualizing Capitalism: Institutions, Evolution, Future, University of Chicago Press, Chicago.). A key question here is whether the corporation can be treated as an agent in itself, or must it be understood solely in terms of the human individuals that make up the organisation. Attention to legal aspects of the firm helps to answer questions concerning the nature and boundary of the firm. Hence it may help to restart progress in the theory of the firm, which has slowed down considerably since 1990.

The concept of transaction costs was originally highlighted by Coase (1937Coase, R.H. (1937), “The nature of the firm”, Economica, Vol. 4 No. 16, New Series, pp. 386-405., 1960Coase, R.H. (1960), “The problem of social cost”, Journal of Law and Economics, Vol. 3 No. 1, pp. 1-44.) and developed further by Williamson (1975Williamson, O.E. (1975), Markets and Hierarchies: Analysis and anti-Trust Implications: A Study in the Economics of Internal Organization, Free Press, New York, NY., 1985Williamson, O.E. (1985), The Economic Institutions of Capitalism: Firms, Markets, Relational Contracting, Macmillan, London.) and others. Transaction costs have been regarded the costs of formulating, negotiating, monitoring and enforcing transactions. Coase’s (1937)Coase, R.H. (1937), “The nature of the firm”, Economica, Vol. 4 No. 16, New Series, pp. 386-405. path-breaking argument was that firms exist when the costs of an alternative market-like arrangement are greater than the costs of operating a firm. Instead of organising production by numerous contracts at every stage of the process, the firm greatly reduces the number and complexity of transactions by placing workers in employment contracts under a single authority. That is why firms exist.

But there is an unresolved dispute between various definitions of transaction cost, which has important analytical consequences (AllenAllen, D.W. (1991), “What are transaction costs?”, Research in Law and Economics 14, pp. 1-18., 1991, 2015Allen, D.W. (2015), “The coase theorem: coherent, logical, and not disproved”, Journal of Institutional Economics, Vol. 11 No. 2, pp. 379-390.; Demsetz, 1968Demsetz, H. (1968), “The cost of transacting”, Quarterly Journal of Economics, Vol. 82 No. 1, pp. 33-53.). Although the concept of transaction cost has been used by Williamson and others in extensive empirical work on contracts and organisational forms, the conceptual underpinnings are still debated. It is difficult to measure transaction costs directly. The many empirical attempts to test various forms of transaction cost analysis have brought mixed results (David and Han, 2004David, R.J. and Han, S.-K. (2004), “A systematic assessment of the empirical support for transaction cost economics”, Strategic Management Journal, Vol. 25 No. 1, pp. 39-58.; Carter and Hodgson, 2006Carter, R. and Hodgson, G.M. (2006), “The impact of empirical tests of transaction cost economics on the debate on the nature of the firm”, Strategic Management Journal, Vol. 27 No. 5, pp. 461-476.).

In clarifying and developing key concepts, institutional research needs to look at legal forms and to use insights from philosophy and elsewhere on how to refine and operationalise these categories.

4.

A future for institutional research

Institutions are the stuff of socio-economic life. Accordingly, the study of the role of institutions in the economy is likely to remain a central topic in the social sciences. In developed economies, the question of institutional design is of major importance. It impacts government policy and is vital in the development of business organisations. We also need to understand better the ways in which economic, political, legal and customary institutions interact and contribute to economic development.

If institutional research were to become more established as an interdisciplinary field of study, its agenda should address the following issues. First, there is the need to develop empirical databases to test institutional theories. Many of the successful recent pieces of research in institutional analysis have used empirical databases to test various propositions regarding the influence of different types of institution over economic performance. The development, refinement and use of empirical databases measuring institutional features will remain an important activity for institutional research.

Second, many of the disputes and inconclusive arguments within institutional research entail different definitions or understandings of key concepts, such as institution, property or transaction cost. More effort should be devoted to conceptual clarification – recruiting insights from philosophy and social theory – to establish more of a consensus and common understanding concerning these core concepts.

Third, institutional researchers need to build bridges between the disciplines involved. Many previous institutional researchers, including Veblen and North, emphasised the importance of delving into psychology, to obtain a deeper understanding of human motivation and of the reasons for following or breaking institutional rules. The importance of political science is widely recognised, and to a lesser extent sociology and anthropology. We should also follow Commons and others, in paying closer attention to the role of law in the economy. Last but not least, philosophy has also made a major recent contribution to our understanding of rules and institutions, and philosophy generally will remain important for institutional research.

Fourth, institutional researchers, from Veblen to North, understood the importance of developing an understanding of the mechanisms of institutional change. This remains an important unfinished task on the agenda. Institutional research may be able to make further progress by bringing in insights from evolutionary theory and from the study of complexity.

Fifth, the interaction between institutions and other factors, particularly technology, needs to be better understood. While some progress has been made in this area, there needs to be more dialogue and cooperation between the study of technology and the study of institutions. We need to understand the similarities, differences and interactions between these two domains of evolution.

Finally, the policy implications of institutional analysis need to be developed, particularly by gaining further insights concerning the nature and role of key institutions such as markets, property rights, corporations and the state.

References

  • Acemoglu, D., Johnson, S. and Robinson, J.A. (2005), “Institutions as a fundamental cause of long-run growth”, in Aghion, P. and Durlauf, S.N. (Eds), Handbook of Economic Growth: Volume 1A, Elsevier, Amsterdam, pp. 385-472.
  • Alchian, A.A. (1977), “Some implications of recognition of property right transaction costs”, in Brunner, K. (Ed.), Economics and Social Institutions: Insights from the Conferences on Analysis and Ideology, Martinus Nijhoff, Boston, MA, pp. 234-255.
  • Allen, D.W. (1991), “What are transaction costs?”, Research in Law and Economics 14, pp. 1-18.
  • Allen, D.W. (2015), “The coase theorem: coherent, logical, and not disproved”, Journal of Institutional Economics, Vol. 11 No. 2, pp. 379-390.
  • Aoki, M. (2001), Toward a Comparative Institutional Analysis, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
  • Barzel, Y. (1989), Economic Analysis of Property Rights, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
  • Barzel, Y. (1994), “The capture of wealth by monopolists and the protection of property rights”, International Review of Law and Economics, Vol. 14 No. 4, pp. 393-409.
  • Camic, C. (1986), “The matter of habit”, American Journal of Sociology, Vol. 91 No. 5, pp. 1039-1087.
  • Carter, R. and Hodgson, G.M. (2006), “The impact of empirical tests of transaction cost economics on the debate on the nature of the firm”, Strategic Management Journal, Vol. 27 No. 5, pp. 461-476.
  • Coase, R.H. (1937), “The nature of the firm”, Economica, Vol. 4 No. 16, New Series, pp. 386-405.
  • Coase, R.H. (1959), “The federal communications commission”, Journal of Law and Economics, Vol. 2 No. 1, pp. 1-40.
  • Coase, R.H. (1960), “The problem of social cost”, Journal of Law and Economics, Vol. 3 No. 1, pp. 1-44.
  • Commons, J.R. (1924), Legal Foundations of Capitalism, Macmillan, New York, NY.
  • David, R.J. and Han, S.-K. (2004), “A systematic assessment of the empirical support for transaction cost economics”, Strategic Management Journal, Vol. 25 No. 1, pp. 39-58.
  • Deakin, S., Gindis, D., Hodgson, G.M., Huang, K. and Pistor, K. (2017), “Legal institutionalism: capitalism and the constitutive role of law”, Journal of Comparative Economics, Vol. 45 No. 1, pp. 188-200.
  • Demsetz, H. (1968), “The cost of transacting”, Quarterly Journal of Economics, Vol. 82 No. 1, pp. 33-53.
  • Dewey, J. (1922), Human Nature and Conduct: An Introduction to Social Psychology, 1st ed., Holt, New York, NY.
  • Gindis, D. (2016), “Legal personhood and the firm: avoiding anthropomorphism and equivocation”, Journal of Institutional Economics, Vol. 12 No. 3, pp. 499-513.
  • Guala, F. (2016), Understanding Institutions: The Science and Philosophy of Living Together, Princeton University Press, Princeton and London.
  • Heinsohn, G. and Steiger, O. (2013), Ownership Economics: On the Foundations of Interest, Money, Markets, Business Cycles and Economic Development, translated and edited by Frank Decker, Routledge, London and New York, NY.
  • Hindriks, F. and Guala, F. (2015), “Institutions, rules, and equilibria: a unified theory”, Journal of Institutional Economics, Vol. 11 No. 3, pp. 459-480.
  • Hodgson, G.M. (2006), “What are institutions?”, Journal of Economic Issues, Vol. 40 No. 1, pp. 1-25.
  • Hodgson, G.M. (2010), “Choice, habit and evolution”, Journal of Evolutionary Economics, Vol. 20 No. 1, pp. 1-18.
  • Hodgson, G.M. (2013), From Pleasure Machines to Moral Communities: An Evolutionary Economics without Homo Economicus, University of Chicago Press, Chicago.
  • Hodgson, G.M. (2015a), Conceptualizing Capitalism: Institutions, Evolution, Future, University of Chicago Press, Chicago.
  • Hodgson, G.M. (2015b), “On defining institutions: rules versus equilibria”, Journal of Institutional Economics, Vol. 11 No. 3, pp. 499-505.
  • Hodgson, G.M. (2015c), “Much of the ‘Economics of property rights’ devalues property and legal rights”, Journal of Institutional Economics, Vol. 11 No. 4, pp. 683-709.
  • Hodgson, G.M. (2017), “1688 and all that: property rights, the glorious revolution and the rise of British capitalism”, Journal of Institutional Economics, Vol. 13 No. 1, pp. 79-107.
  • Hodgson, G.M. (2019), “Taxonomic definitions in social science, with firms, markets and institutions as case studies”, Journal of Institutional Economics, (forthcoming).
  • Hodgson, G.M. and Knudsen, T. (2004), “The complex evolution of a simple traffic convention: the functions and implications of habit”, Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, Vol. 54 No. 1, pp. 19-47.
  • Honoré, A.M. (1961), “Ownership”, in Guest, A.G. (Ed.), Oxford Essays in Jurisprudence, Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp. 107-147, Reprinted in the Journal of Institutional Economics, Vol. 9 No. 2, June 2013, pp. 227-255.
  • Knight, J. (1992), Institutions and Social Conflict, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
  • La Porta, R., Lopez-de-Silanes, F. and Shleifer, A. (2008), “The economic consequences of legal origins”, Journal of Economic Literature¸, Vol. 46 No. 2, pp. 285-332.
  • La Porta, R., Lopez-de-Silanes, F., Shleifer, A. and Vishny, R. (1999), “The quality of government”, Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, Vol. 15 No. 1, pp. 222-279.
  • Lukes, S. (1974), Power: A Radical View, Macmillan, London.
  • Martin, B.R. (2012), “The evolution of science policy and innovation studies”, Research Policy, Vol. 41 No. 7, pp. 1219-1239.
  • Nelson, R. and Sampat, B.N. (2001), “Making sense of institutions as a factor shaping economic performance”, Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, Vol. 44 No. 1, pp. 31-54.
  • North, D.C. (1971), “Institutional change and economic growth”, The Journal of Economic History, Vol. 31 No. 1, pp. 118-125.
  • North, D.C. (1981), Structure and Change in Economic History, Norton, New York, NY.
  • North, D.C. (1990), Institutions, Institutional Change and Economic Performance, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge and New York, NY.
  • North, D.C. (1994), “Economic performance through time”, American Economic Review, Vol. 84 No. 3, pp. 359-367.
  • Ostrom, E. (1990), Governing the Commons: The Evolution of Institutions for Collective Action, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
  • Ouellette, J.A. and Wood, W. (1998), “Habit and intention in everyday life: the multiple processes by which past behavior predicts future behavior”, Psychological Bulletin, Vol. 124 No. 1, pp. 54-74.
  • Powell, W.W. and DiMaggio, PJ. (Eds) (1991), The New Institutionalism in Organizational Analysis, University of Chicago Press, Chicago and London.
  • Scott, W.R. (1995), Institutions and Organizations, Sage, Thousand Oaks, CA and London.
  • Searle, J.R. (1995), The Construction of Social Reality, Allen Lane, London.
  • Sen, A.K. (1987), On Ethics and Economics, Basil Blackwell, Oxford and New York, NY.
  • Simon, H.A. (1957), Models of Man: Social and Rational. Mathematical Essays on Rational Human Behavior in a Social Setting, Wiley, New York, NY.
  • Simon, H.A. (1979), “Rational decision making in business organizations”, American Economic Review, Vol. 69 No. 4, pp. 493-513.
  • Smith, A. (1759), The Theory of Moral Sentiments; or, An Essay towards an Analysis of the Principles by Which Men Naturally Judge concerning the Conduct and Character, First of Their Neighbours, and Afterwards of Themselves, Millar, and Kincaid and Bell, London and Edinburgh.
  • Smith, V.L. (2013), “Adam smith: from propriety and sentiments to property and wealth”, Forum for Social Economics, Vol. 42 No. 4, pp. 283-297.
  • Tyler, T.R. (1990), Why People Obey the Law, Yale University Press, New Haven.
  • Veblen, T.B. (1899), The Theory of the Leisure Class: An Economic Study in the Evolution of Institutions, Macmillan, New York, NY.
  • Veblen, T.B. (1914), The Instinct of Workmanship, and the State of the Industrial Arts, Macmillan, New York, NY.
  • Williamson, O.E. (1975), Markets and Hierarchies: Analysis and anti-Trust Implications: A Study in the Economics of Internal Organization, Free Press, New York, NY.
  • Williamson, O.E. (1985), The Economic Institutions of Capitalism: Firms, Markets, Relational Contracting, Macmillan, London.
  • Wood, W., Quinn, J.M. and Kashy, D. (2002), “Habits in everyday life: thought, emotion, and action”, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, Vol. 83 No. 6, pp. 1281-1297.

Publication Dates

  • Publication in this collection
    11 Feb 2019
  • Date of issue
    Jan-Mar 2019

History

  • Received
    07 Nov 2018
  • Reviewed
    07 Nov 2018
  • Accepted
    08 Nov 2018
Universidade de São Paulo Avenida Professor Luciano Gualberto, 908, sala F184, CEP: 05508-900, São Paulo , SP - Brasil, Telefone: (11) 3818-4002 - São Paulo - SP - Brazil
E-mail: rausp@usp.br